Intuitionistic type theory (also known as constructive type theory, or Martin-Löf type theory) is a
type theory
In mathematics, logic, and computer science, a type theory is the formal presentation of a specific type system, and in general type theory is the academic study of type systems. Some type theories serve as alternatives to set theory as a foundat ...
and an alternative
foundation of mathematics
Foundations of mathematics is the study of the philosophical and logical and/or algorithmic basis of mathematics, or, in a broader sense, the mathematical investigation of what underlies the philosophical theories concerning the nature of mathe ...
.
Intuitionistic type theory was created by
Per Martin-Löf
Per Erik Rutger Martin-Löf (; ; born 8 May 1942) is a Swedish logician, philosopher, and mathematical statistician. He is internationally renowned for his work on the foundations of probability, statistics, mathematical logic, and computer scie ...
, a
Swedish
Swedish or ' may refer to:
Anything from or related to Sweden, a country in Northern Europe. Or, specifically:
* Swedish language, a North Germanic language spoken primarily in Sweden and Finland
** Swedish alphabet, the official alphabet used by ...
mathematician
A mathematician is someone who uses an extensive knowledge of mathematics in their work, typically to solve mathematical problems.
Mathematicians are concerned with numbers, data, quantity, structure, space, models, and change.
History
On ...
and
philosopher
A philosopher is a person who practices or investigates philosophy. The term ''philosopher'' comes from the grc, φιλόσοφος, , translit=philosophos, meaning 'lover of wisdom'. The coining of the term has been attributed to the Greek th ...
, who first published it in 1972. There are multiple versions of the type theory: Martin-Löf proposed both intensional and
extensional In any of several fields of study that treat the use of signs — for example, in linguistics, logic, mathematics, semantics, semiotics, and philosophy of language — an extensional context (or transparent context) is a syntactic environment in w ...
variants of the theory and early
impredicative
In mathematics, logic and philosophy of mathematics, something that is impredicative is a self-referencing definition. Roughly speaking, a definition is impredicative if it invokes (mentions or quantifies over) the set being defined, or (more com ...
versions, shown to be inconsistent by
Girard's paradox
In mathematical logic, System U and System U− are pure type systems, i.e. special forms of a typed lambda calculus with an arbitrary number of sorts, axioms and rules (or dependencies between the sorts). They were both proved inconsistent by Je ...
, gave way to predicative versions. However, all versions keep the core design of constructive logic using
dependent types
In computer science and logic, a dependent type is a type whose definition depends on a value. It is an overlapping feature of type theory and type systems. In intuitionistic type theory, dependent types are used to encode logic's quantifiers lik ...
.
Design
Martin-Löf designed the type theory on the principles of mathematical constructivism. Constructivism requires any existence proof to contain a "witness". So, any proof of "there exists a prime greater than 1000" must identify a specific number that is both prime and greater than 1000. Intuitionistic type theory accomplished this design goal by internalizing the
BHK interpretation BHK is a three-letter abbreviation that may refer to:
* BHK interpretation of intuitionistic predicate logic
* Baby hamster kidney cells used in molecular biology
* Bachelor of Human Kinetics (BHk) degree.
* Baltische Historische Kommission, organi ...
. An interesting consequence is that proofs become mathematical objects that can be examined, compared, and manipulated.
Intuitionistic type theory's type constructors were built to follow a one-to-one correspondence with logical connectives. For example, the logical connective called implication () corresponds to the type of a function (). This correspondence is called the Curry–Howard isomorphism. Previous type theories had also followed this isomorphism, but Martin-Löf's was the first to extend it to predicate logic by introducing dependent types.
Type theory
Intuitionistic type theory has 3 finite types, which are then composed using 5 different type constructors. Unlike set theories, type theories are not built on top of a logic like Frege's. So, each feature of the type theory does double duty as a feature of both math and logic.
''If you are unfamiliar with type theory and know set theory, a quick summary is: Types contain terms just like sets contain elements. Terms belong to one and only one type. Terms like and compute ("reduce") down to canonical terms like 4. For more, see the article on
Type theory
In mathematics, logic, and computer science, a type theory is the formal presentation of a specific type system, and in general type theory is the academic study of type systems. Some type theories serve as alternatives to set theory as a foundat ...
.''
0 type, 1 type and 2 type
There are 3 finite types: The 0 type contains 0 terms. The 1 type contains 1 canonical term. And the 2 type contains 2 canonical terms.
Because the 0 type contains 0 terms, it is also called the
empty type In type theory, the empty type or absurd type, typically denoted \mathbb 0 is a type with no terms. Such a type may be defined as the nullary coproduct (i.e. disjoint sum of no types). It may also be defined as the polymorphic type \forall t.t
For ...
. It is used to represent anything that cannot exist. It is also written and represents anything unprovable. (That is, a proof of it cannot exist.) As a result,
negation
In logic, negation, also called the logical complement, is an operation that takes a proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P or \overline. It is interpreted intuitively as being true when P is false, and false ...
is defined as a function to it: .
Likewise, the 1 type contains 1 canonical term and represents existence. It also is called the unit type. It often represents propositions that can be proven and is, therefore, sometimes written .
Finally, the 2 type contains 2 canonical terms. It represents a definite choice between two values. It is used for Boolean values but ''not'' propositions. Propositions are considered the 1 type and may be proven to never have a proof (the 0 type), or may not be proven either way. (The Law of Excluded Middle does not hold for propositions in intuitionistic type theory.)
Σ type constructor
Σ-types contain ordered pairs. As with typical ordered pair (or 2-tuple) types, a Σ-type can describe the
Cartesian product
In mathematics, specifically set theory, the Cartesian product of two sets ''A'' and ''B'', denoted ''A''×''B'', is the set of all ordered pairs where ''a'' is in ''A'' and ''b'' is in ''B''. In terms of set-builder notation, that is
: A\ti ...
, , of two other types, and . Logically, such an ordered pair would hold a proof of and a proof of , so one may see such a type written as .
Σ-types are more powerful than typical ordered pair types because of dependent typing. In the ordered pair, the type of the second term can depend on the value of the first term. For example, the first term of the pair might be a natural number and the second term's type might be a vector of length equal to the first term. Such a type would be written:
:
Using set-theory terminology, this is similar to an indexed disjoint unions of sets. In the case of usual ordered pairs, the type of the second term does not depend on the value of the first term. Thus the type describing the cartesian product is written:
:
It is important to note here that the value of the first term, , is not depended on by the type of the second term, .
Σ-types can be used to build up longer dependently-typed
tuple
In mathematics, a tuple is a finite ordered list (sequence) of elements. An -tuple is a sequence (or ordered list) of elements, where is a non-negative integer. There is only one 0-tuple, referred to as ''the empty tuple''. An -tuple is defi ...
s used in mathematics and the records or structs used in most programming languages. An example of a dependently-typed 3-tuple is two integers and a proof that the first integer is smaller than the second integer, described by the type:
:
Dependent typing allows Σ-types to serve the role of existential quantifier. The statement "there exists an of type , such that is proven" becomes the type of ordered pairs where the first item is the value of type and the second item is a proof of . Notice that the type of the second item (proofs of ) depends on the value in the first part of the ordered pair (). Its type would be:
:
Π type constructor
Π-types contain functions. As with typical function types, they consist of an input type and an output type. They are more powerful than typical function types however, in that the return type can depend on the input value. Functions in type theory are different from set theory. In set theory, you look up the argument's value in a set of ordered pairs. In type theory, the argument is substituted into a term and then computation ("reduction") is applied to the term.
As an example, the type of a function that, given a natural number , returns a vector containing real numbers is written:
:
When the output type does not depend on the input value, the function type is often simply written with a . Thus, is the type of functions from natural numbers to real numbers. Such Π-types correspond to logical implication. The logical proposition corresponds to the type , containing functions that take proofs-of-A and return proofs-of-B. This type could be written more consistently as:
:
Π-types are also used in logic for
universal quantification
In mathematical logic, a universal quantification is a type of quantifier, a logical constant which is interpreted as "given any" or "for all". It expresses that a predicate can be satisfied by every member of a domain of discourse. In other w ...
. The statement "for every of type , is proven" becomes a function from of type to proofs of . Thus, given the value for the function generates a proof that holds for that value. The type would be
:
= type constructor
=-types are created from two terms. Given two terms like and , you can create a new type . The terms of that new type represent proofs that the pair reduce to the same canonical term. Thus, since both and compute to the canonical term , there will be a term of the type . In intuitionistic type theory, there is a single way to make terms of =-types and that is by reflexivity:
:
It is possible to create =-types such as where the terms do not reduce to the same canonical term, but you will be unable to create terms of that new type. In fact, if you were able to create a term of , you could create a term of . Putting that into a function would generate a function of type . Since is how intuitionistic type theory defines negation, you would have or, finally, .
Equality of proofs is an area of active research in
proof theory
Proof theory is a major branchAccording to Wang (1981), pp. 3–4, proof theory is one of four domains mathematical logic, together with model theory, axiomatic set theory, and recursion theory. Jon Barwise, Barwise (1978) consists of four correspo ...
Inductive types allow the creation of complex, self-referential types. For example, a linked list of natural numbers is either an empty list or a pair of a natural number and another linked list. Inductive types can be used to define unbounded mathematical structures like trees, graphs, etc.. In fact, the natural numbers type may be defined as an inductive type, either being or the successor of another natural number.
Inductive types define new constants, such as zero and the successor function . Since does not have a definition and cannot be evaluated using substitution, terms like
and become the canonical terms of the natural numbers.
Proofs on inductive types are made possible by
induction
Induction, Inducible or Inductive may refer to:
Biology and medicine
* Labor induction (birth/pregnancy)
* Induction chemotherapy, in medicine
* Induced stem cells, stem cells derived from somatic, reproductive, pluripotent or other cell t ...
. Each new inductive type comes with its own inductive rule. To prove a predicate for every natural number, you use the following rule:
:
Inductive types in intuitionistic type theory are defined in terms of W-types, the type of
well-founded
In mathematics, a binary relation ''R'' is called well-founded (or wellfounded) on a class ''X'' if every non-empty subset ''S'' ⊆ ''X'' has a minimal element with respect to ''R'', that is, an element ''m'' not related by ''s& ...
trees. Later work in type theory generated coinductive types, induction-recursion, and induction-induction for working on types with more obscure kinds of self-referentiality.
Higher inductive type
In mathematical logic and computer science, homotopy type theory (HoTT ) refers to various lines of development of intuitionistic type theory, based on the interpretation of types as objects to which the intuition of (abstract) homotopy theory a ...
s allow equality to be defined between terms.
Universe types
The universe types allow proofs to be written about all the types created with the other type constructors. Every term in the universe type can be mapped to a type created with any combination of and the inductive type constructor. However, to avoid paradoxes, there is no term in that maps to .
To write proofs about all "the small types" and , you must use , which does contain a term for , but not for itself . Similarly, for . There is a predicative hierarchy of universes, so to quantify a proof over any fixed constant universes, you can use .
Universe types are a tricky feature of type theories. Martin-Löf's original type theory had to be changed to account for
Girard's paradox
In mathematical logic, System U and System U− are pure type systems, i.e. special forms of a typed lambda calculus with an arbitrary number of sorts, axioms and rules (or dependencies between the sorts). They were both proved inconsistent by Je ...
. Later research covered topics such as "super universes", "Mahlo universes", and impredicative universes.
Judgements
The formal definition of intuitionistic type theory is written using judgements. For example, in the statement "if is a type and is a type then is a type" there are judgements of "is a type", "and", and "if ... then ...". The expression is not a judgement; it is the type being defined.
This second level of the type theory can be confusing, particularly where it comes to equality. There is a judgement of term equality, which might say . It is a statement that two terms reduce to the same canonical term. There is also a judgement of type equality, say that , which means every element of is an element of the type and vice versa. At the type level, there is a type and it contains terms if there is a proof that and reduce to the same value. (Terms of this type are generated using the term-equality judgement.) Lastly, there is an English-language level of equality, because we use the word "four" and symbol "" to refer to the canonical term . Synonyms like these are called "definitionally equal" by Martin-Löf.
The description of judgements below is based on the discussion in Nordström, Petersson, and Smith.
The formal theory works with ''types'' and ''objects''.
A type is declared by:
*
An object exists and is in a type if:
*
Objects can be equal
*
and types can be equal
*
A type that depends on an object from another type is declared
*
and removed by substitution
* , replacing the variable with the object in .
An object that depends on an object from another type can be done two ways.
If the object is "abstracted", then it is written
*
and removed by substitution
* , replacing the variable with the object in .
The object-depending-on-object can also be declared as a constant as part of a recursive type. An example of a recursive type is:
*
*
Here, is a constant object-depending-on-object. It is not associated with an abstraction.
Constants like can be removed by defining equality. Here the relationship with addition is defined using equality and using pattern matching to handle the recursive aspect of :
:
is manipulated as an opaque constant - it has no internal structure for substitution.
So, objects and types and these relations are used to express formulae in the theory. The following styles of judgements are used to create new objects, types and relations from existing ones:
By convention, there is a type that represents all other types. It is called (or ). Since is a type, the members of it are objects. There is a dependent type that maps each object to its corresponding type. ''In most texts is never written.'' From the context of the statement, a reader can almost always tell whether refers to a type, or whether it refers to the object in that corresponds to the type.
This is the complete foundation of the theory. Everything else is derived.
To implement logic, each proposition is given its own type. The objects in those types represent the different possible ways to prove the proposition. If there is no proof for the proposition, then the type has no objects in it. Operators like "and" and "or" that work on propositions introduce new types and new objects. So is a type that depends on the type and the type . The objects in that dependent type are defined to exist for every pair of objects in and . If or has no proof and is an empty type, then the new type representing is also empty.
This can be done for other types (booleans, natural numbers, etc.) and their operators.
Categorical models of type theory
Using the language of
category theory
Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations that was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Nowadays, cate ...
,
R. A. G. Seely
R. or r. may refer to:
* ''Reign'', the period of time during which an Emperor, king, queen, etc., is ruler.
* '' Rex'', abbreviated as R., the Latin word meaning King
* ''Regina'', abbreviated as R., the Latin word meaning Queen
* or , abbreviat ...
introduced the notion of a
locally cartesian closed category
In category theory, a category is Cartesian closed if, roughly speaking, any morphism defined on a product of two objects can be naturally identified with a morphism defined on one of the factors. These categories are particularly important in ma ...
(LCCC) as the basic model of type theory. This has been refined by Hofmann and Dybjer to ''Categories with Families'' or ''Categories with Attributes'' based on earlier work by Cartmell.
A category with families is a category ''C'' of contexts (in which the objects are contexts, and
the context morphisms are substitutions), together with a functor ''T'' : ''C''op → ''Fam''(''Set'').
''Fam''(''Set'') is the category of families of Sets, in which objects are pairs of an "index set" ''A'' and a function ''B'': ''X'' → ''A'', and morphisms are pairs of functions ''f'' : ''A'' → ''A' '' and ''g'' : ''X'' → ''X' '', such that ''B' '' ° ''g'' = ''f'' ° ''B'' in other words, ''f'' maps ''Ba'' to ''B''''g''(''a'').
The functor ''T'' assigns to a context ''G'' a set of types, and for each , a set of terms.
The axioms for a functor require that these play harmoniously with substitution. Substitution is usually
written in the form ''Af'' or ''af'', where ''A'' is a type in and ''a'' is a term in , and ''f'' is a substitution
from ''D'' to ''G''. Here and .
The category ''C'' must contain a terminal object (the empty context), and a final object for a form
of product called comprehension, or context extension, in which the right element is a type in the context of the left element.
If ''G'' is a context, and , then there should be an object final among
contexts ''D'' with mappings ''p'' : ''D'' → ''G'', ''q'' : ''Tm''(''D,Ap'').
A logical framework, such as Martin-Löf's takes the form of
closure conditions on the context dependent sets of types and terms: that there should be a type called
Set, and for each set a type, that the types should be closed under forms of dependent sum and
product, and so forth.
A theory such as that of predicative set theory expresses closure conditions on the types of sets and
their elements: that they should be closed under operations that reflect dependent sum and product,
and under various forms of inductive definition.
Extensional versus intensional
A fundamental distinction is
extensional In any of several fields of study that treat the use of signs — for example, in linguistics, logic, mathematics, semantics, semiotics, and philosophy of language — an extensional context (or transparent context) is a syntactic environment in w ...
vs intensional type theory. In extensional type theory definitional (i.e., computational) equality is not distinguished from propositional equality, which requires proof. As a consequence type checking becomes undecidable in extensional type theory because programs in the theory might not terminate. For example, such a theory allows one to give a type to the
Y-combinator
Y Combinator (YC) is an American technology startup accelerator launched in March 2005. It has been used to launch more than 3,000 companies, including Airbnb, Coinbase, Cruise, DoorDash, Dropbox, Instacart, Quora, PagerDuty, Reddit, Stri ...
; a detailed example of this can be found in Nordstöm and Petersson ''Programming in Martin-Löf's Type Theory''. However, this does not prevent extensional type theory from being a basis for a practical tool; for example, NuPRL is based on extensional type theory.
In contrast in intensional type theory type checking is decidable, but the representation of standard mathematical concepts is somewhat more cumbersome, since intensional reasoning requires using setoids or similar constructions. There are many common mathematical objects which are hard to work with or cannot be represented without this, for example,
integer numbers
An integer is the number zero (), a positive natural number (, , , etc.) or a negative integer with a minus sign (−1, −2, −3, etc.). The negative numbers are the additive inverses of the corresponding positive numbers. In the language o ...
,
rational number
In mathematics, a rational number is a number that can be expressed as the quotient or fraction of two integers, a numerator and a non-zero denominator . For example, is a rational number, as is every integer (e.g. ). The set of all ration ...
s, and
real number
In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a ''continuous'' one-dimensional quantity such as a distance, duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that values can have arbitrarily small variations. Every real ...
s. Integers and rational numbers can be represented without setoids, but this representation is difficult to work with. Cauchy real numbers cannot be represented without this.
Homotopy type theory works on resolving this problem. It allows one to define
higher inductive type
In mathematical logic and computer science, homotopy type theory (HoTT ) refers to various lines of development of intuitionistic type theory, based on the interpretation of types as objects to which the intuition of (abstract) homotopy theory a ...
s, which not only define first order constructors (
value
Value or values may refer to:
Ethics and social
* Value (ethics) wherein said concept may be construed as treating actions themselves as abstract objects, associating value to them
** Values (Western philosophy) expands the notion of value beyo ...
s or
point
Point or points may refer to:
Places
* Point, Lewis, a peninsula in the Outer Hebrides, Scotland
* Point, Texas, a city in Rains County, Texas, United States
* Point, the NE tip and a ferry terminal of Lismore, Inner Hebrides, Scotland
* Point ...
s), but higher order constructors, i.e. equalities between elements (
path
A path is a route for physical travel – see Trail.
Path or PATH may also refer to:
Physical paths of different types
* Bicycle path
* Bridle path, used by people on horseback
* Course (navigation), the intended path of a vehicle
* Desire p ...
s), equalities between equalities ( homotopies), ''ad infinitum''.
Implementations of type theory
Different forms of type theory have been implemented as the formal systems underlying of a number of
proof assistant
In computer science and mathematical logic, a proof assistant or interactive theorem prover is a software tool to assist with the development of formal proofs by human-machine collaboration. This involves some sort of interactive proof editor ...
s. While many are based on Per Martin-Löf's ideas, many have added features, more axioms, or different philosophical background. For instance, the NuPRL system is based on
computational type theory
Computation is any type of arithmetic or non-arithmetic calculation that follows a well-defined model (e.g., an algorithm).
Mechanical or electronic devices (or, historically, people) that perform computations are known as '' computers''. An ...
ATS
ATS or Ats may refer to:
Businesses
* ATS Wheels, or ''Auto Technisches Spezialzubehör'', a German wheel manufacturer and sponsor of a Formula One racing team
* ATS Automation Tooling Systems, an Ontario, Canada-based factory automation company
...
,
Cayenne
Cayenne (; ; gcr, Kayenn) is the capital city of French Guiana, an overseas region and Overseas department, department of France located in South America. The city stands on a former island at the mouth of the Cayenne River on the Atlantic Oc ...
,
Epigram
An epigram is a brief, interesting, memorable, and sometimes surprising or satirical statement. The word is derived from the Greek "inscription" from "to write on, to inscribe", and the literary device has been employed for over two mille ...
,
Agda Agda may refer to:
* Agda (programming language), the programming language and theorem prover
* Agda (Golgafrinchan), the character in ''The Hitchhiker's Guide to the Galaxy'' by Douglas Adams
* Liten Agda, the heroine of a Swedish legend
* Agda M ...
, and
Idris Idris may refer to:
People
* Idris (name), a list of people and fictional characters with the given name or surname
* Idris (prophet), Islamic prophet in the Qur'an, traditionally identified with Enoch, an ancestor of Noah in the Bible
* Idris G ...
.
Martin-Löf type theories
Per Martin-Löf
Per Erik Rutger Martin-Löf (; ; born 8 May 1942) is a Swedish logician, philosopher, and mathematical statistician. He is internationally renowned for his work on the foundations of probability, statistics, mathematical logic, and computer scie ...
constructed several type theories that were published at various times, some of them much later than when the preprints with their description became accessible to the specialists (among others Jean-Yves Girard and Giovanni Sambin). The list below attempts to list all the theories that have been described in a printed form and to sketch the key features that distinguished them from each other. All of these theories had dependent products, dependent sums, disjoint unions, finite types and natural numbers. All the theories had the same reduction rules that did not include η-reduction either for dependent products or for dependent sums, except for MLTT79 where the η-reduction for dependent products is added.
MLTT71 was the first of type theories created by Per Martin-Löf. It appeared in a preprint in 1971. It had one universe but this universe had a name in itself, i.e. it was a type theory with, as it is called today, "Type in Type". Jean-Yves Girard has shown that this system was inconsistent and the preprint was never published.
MLTT72 was presented in a 1972 preprint that has now been published. That theory had one universe V and no identity types. The universe was " predicative" in the sense that the dependent product of a family of objects from V over an object that was not in V such as, for example, V itself, was not assumed to be in V. The universe was à la Russell's '' Principia Mathematica'', i.e., one would write directly "T∈V" and "t∈T" (Martin-Löf uses the sign "∈" instead of modern ":") without the additional constructor such as "El".
MLTT73 was the first definition of a type theory that Per Martin-Löf published (it was presented at the Logic Colloquium '73 and published in 1975). There are identity types which he calls "propositions" but since no real distinction between propositions and the rest of the types is introduced the meaning of this is unclear. There is what later acquires the name of J-eliminator but yet without a name (see pp. 94–95). There is in this theory an infinite sequence of universes V0, ..., V''n'', ... . The universes are predicative, à la Russell and ''non-cumulative''. In fact, Corollary 3.10 on p. 115 says that if A∈V''m'' and B∈V''n'' are such that A and B are convertible then ''m'' = ''n''. This means, for example, that it would be difficult to formulate univalence in this theory—there are contractible types in each of the Vi but it is unclear how to declare them to be equal since there are no identity types connecting V''i'' and V''j'' for ''i'' ≠ ''j''.
MLTT79 was presented in 1979 and published in 1982. In this paper, Martin-Löf introduced the four basic types of judgement for the dependent type theory that has since become fundamental in the study of the meta-theory of such systems. He also introduced contexts as a separate concept in it (see p. 161). There are identity types with the J-eliminator (which already appeared in MLTT73 but did not have this name there) but also with the rule that makes the theory "extensional" (p. 169). There are W-types. There is an infinite sequence of predicative universes that ''are cumulative''.
Bibliopolis: there is a discussion of a type theory in the ''Bibliopolis'' book from 1984Per Martin-Löf, "Intuitionistic type theory", ''Studies in Proof Theory'' (lecture notes by Giovanni Sambin), vol. 1, pp. iv+91, 1984 but it is somewhat open-ended and does not seem to represent a particular set of choices and so there is no specific type theory associated with it.
– lecture notes and slides from the Types Summer School 2005
– letter from
John Baez
John Carlos Baez (; born June 12, 1961) is an American mathematical physicist and a professor of mathematics at the University of California, Riverside (UCR) in Riverside, California. He has worked on spin foams in loop quantum gravity, appl ...