HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Connexive logic names one class of alternative, or non-classical, logics designed to exclude the
paradoxes of material implication The paradoxes of material implication are a group of tautology (logic), true formulae involving material conditionals whose translations into natural language are intuitively false when the conditional is translated as "if ... then ...". A material ...
. The characteristic that separates connexive logic from other non-classical logics is its acceptance of Aristotle's thesis, i.e. the formula, * ~(~p → p) as a
logical truth Logical truth is one of the most fundamental concepts in logic. Broadly speaking, a logical truth is a statement which is true regardless of the truth or falsity of its constituent propositions. In other words, a logical truth is a statement whic ...
. Aristotle's thesis asserts that no statement follows from its own denial. Stronger connexive logics also accept Boethius' thesis, * ((p → q) → ~(p → ~q)) which states that if a statement implies one thing, it does not imply its opposite.
Relevance logic Relevance logic, also called relevant logic, is a kind of non-classical logic requiring the antecedent and consequent of implications to be relevantly related. They may be viewed as a family of substructural or modal logics. It is generally, but ...
is another logical theory that tries to avoid the paradoxes of material implication.


History

Connexive logic is arguably one of the oldest approaches to logic. Aristotle's Thesis is named after
Aristotle Aristotle (; grc-gre, Ἀριστοτέλης ''Aristotélēs'', ; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and polymath during the Classical period in Ancient Greece. Taught by Plato, he was the founder of the Peripatetic school of phil ...
because he uses this principle in a passage in the ''Prior Analytics''.
It is impossible that the same thing should be necessitated by the being and the not-being of the same thing. I mean, for example, that it is impossible that B should necessarily be great if A is white, and that B should necessarily be great if A is not white. For if B is not great A cannot be white. But if, when A is not white, it is necessary that B should be great, it necessarily results that if B is not great, B itself is great. But this is impossible. ''An. Pr''. ii 4.57b3.
The sense of this passage is to perform a ''
reductio ad absurdum In logic, (Latin for "reduction to absurdity"), also known as (Latin for "argument to absurdity") or ''apagogical arguments'', is the form of argument that attempts to establish a claim by showing that the opposite scenario would lead to absu ...
'' proof on the claim that two formulas, (A → B) and (~A → B), can be true simultaneously. The proof is, # (A → B) hypothesis # (~A → B) hypothesis # (~B → ~A) 1, Transposition # (~B → B) 2, 3, Hypothetical Syllogism Aristotle then declares step 4 to be impossible, completing the ''reductio''. But if step 4 is impossible, it must be because Aristotle accepts its denial, ~(~B → B), as a logical truth. Aristotelian
syllogisms A syllogism ( grc-gre, συλλογισμός, ''syllogismos'', 'conclusion, inference') is a kind of logical argument that applies deductive reasoning to arrive at a conclusion based on two propositions that are asserted or assumed to be true. ...
(as opposed to Boolean syllogisms) appear to be based on connexive principles. For example, the contrariety of A and E statements, "All S are P," and "No S are P," follows by a ''reductio ad absurdum'' argument similar to the one given by Aristotle. Later logicians, notably
Chrysippus Chrysippus of Soli (; grc-gre, Χρύσιππος ὁ Σολεύς, ; ) was a Greek Stoic philosopher. He was a native of Soli, Cilicia, but moved to Athens as a young man, where he became a pupil of the Stoic philosopher Cleanthes. When Clean ...
, are also thought to have endorsed connexive principles. By 100 C.E. logicians had divided into four or five distinct schools concerning the correct understanding of conditional ("if...then...") statements.
Sextus Empiricus Sextus Empiricus ( grc-gre, Σέξτος Ἐμπειρικός, ; ) was a Ancient Greece, Greek Pyrrhonism, Pyrrhonist philosopher and Empiric school physician. His philosophical works are the most complete surviving account of ancient Greek and ...
described one school as follows.
And those who introduce the notion of connexion say that a conditional is sound when the contradictory of its consequent is incompatible with its antecedent.
The term "connexivism" is derived from this passage (as translated by Kneale and Kneale). It is believed that Sextus was here describing the school of Chrysippus. That this school accepted Aristotle's thesis seems clear because the definition of the conditional, * (p → q) =df ~(p ° ~q) - where ° indicates compatibility, requires that Aristotle's Thesis be a logical truth, provided we assume that every statement is compatible with itself, which seems fairly fundamental to the concept of compatibility. The medieval philosopher
Boethius Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius, commonly known as Boethius (; Latin: ''Boetius''; 480 – 524 AD), was a Roman senator, consul, ''magister officiorum'', historian, and philosopher of the Early Middle Ages. He was a central figure in the tr ...
also accepted connexive principles. In ''De Syllogismo Hypothetico'', he argues that from, "If A, then if B then C," and "If B then not-C," we may infer "not-A," by modus tollens. However, this follows only if the two statements, "If B then C," and "If B then not-C," are considered incompatible. Since Aristotelian logic was the standard logic studied until the 19th Century, it could reasonably be claimed that connexive logic was the accepted school of thought among logicians for most of Western history. (Of course, logicians were not necessarily aware of belonging to the connexivist school.) However, in the 19th Century Boolean syllogisms, and a propositional logic based on truth-functions, became the standard. Since then, relatively few logicians have subscribed to connexivism. These few include E. J. Nelson and
P. F. Strawson Peter Frederick Strawson (; 23 November 1919 – 13 February 2006) was an English philosopher. He was the Waynflete Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy at the University of Oxford (Magdalen College) from 1968 to 1987. Before that, he ...
.


Connecting antecedent to consequent

The objection that is made to the truth-functional definition of conditionals is that there is no requirement that the consequent ''actually follow'' from the antecedent. So long as the antecedent is false or the consequent true, the conditional is considered to be true whether there is any relation between the antecedent and the consequent or not. Hence, as the philosopher
Charles Sanders Peirce Charles Sanders Peirce ( ; September 10, 1839 – April 19, 1914) was an American philosopher, logician, mathematician and scientist who is sometimes known as "the father of pragmatism". Educated as a chemist and employed as a scientist for t ...
once remarked, you can cut up a newspaper, sentence by sentence, put all the sentences in a hat, and draw any two at random. It is guaranteed that either the first sentence will imply the second, or vice versa. But when we use the words "if" and "then" we generally mean to assert that there is some relation between the antecedent and the consequent. What is the nature of that relationship? Relevance (or relevant) logicians take the view that, in addition to saying that the consequent cannot be false while the antecedent is true, the antecedent must be "relevant" to the consequent. At least initially, this means that there must be at least some terms (or variables) that appear in both the antecedent and the consequent. Connexivists generally claim instead that there must be some "real connection" between the antecedent and the consequent, such as might be the result of real class inclusion relations. For example, the class relations, "All men are mortal," would provide a real connection that would warrant the conditional, "If Socrates is a man, then Socrates is mortal." However, more remote connections, for example "If she apologized to him, then he lied to me." (suggested by Bennett) still defy connexivist analysis.


Notes


References

* Angell R. B. ''A-Logic'', Washington: University Press of America, 2002. * Bennett, J. ''A Philosophical Guide to Conditionals''. Oxford: Clarendon, 2003. * Kneale, M. and Kneale, W. ''The Development of Logic''. Oxford: Clarendon, 1984. * McCall, S. "Connexive Implication", ''The Journal of Symbolic Logic'', Vol. 31, No. 3 (1966), pp. 415 - 433. * Nasti de Vincentis, M. ''Logiche della connessività. Fra logica moderna e storia della logica antica''. Bern: Haupt, 2002.


External links

* {{Non-classical logic Non-classical logic