Types of completeness properties
All completeness properties are described along a similar scheme: one describes a certain class of subsets of a partially ordered set that are required to have a supremum or required to have an infimum. Hence every completeness property has its dual, obtained by inverting the order-dependent definitions in the given statement. Some of the notions are usually not dualized while others may be self-dual (i.e. equivalent to their dual statements).Least and greatest elements
The easiest example of a supremum is the empty one, i.e. the supremum of theFinite completeness
Further simple completeness conditions arise from the consideration of all non-empty finite sets. An order in which all non-empty finite sets have both a supremum and an infimum is called a lattice. It suffices to require that all suprema and infima of ''two'' elements exist to obtain all non-empty finite ones; a straightforward induction argument shows that every finite non-empty supremum/infimum can be decomposed into a finite number of binary suprema/infima. Thus the central operations of lattices are binary suprema and infima It is in this context that the terms meet for and join for are most common. A poset in which only non-empty finite suprema are known to exist is therefore called a join-semilattice. The dual notion is meet-semilattice.Further completeness conditions
The strongest form of completeness is the existence of all suprema and all infima. The posets with this property are the complete lattices. However, using the given order, one can restrict to further classes of (possibly infinite) subsets, that do not yield this strong completeness at once. If all directed subsets of a poset have a supremum, then the order is a directed-complete partial order (dcpo). These are especially important in domain theory. The seldom-considered dual notion to a dcpo is the filtered-complete poset. Dcpos with a least element ("pointed dcpos") are one of the possible meanings of the phrase complete partial order (cpo). If every subset that has ''some'' upper bound has also a least upper bound, then the respective poset is called bounded complete. The term is used widely with this definition that focuses on suprema and there is no common name for the dual property. However, bounded completeness can be expressed in terms of other completeness conditions that are easily dualized (see below). Although concepts with the names "complete" and "bounded" were already defined, confusion is unlikely to occur since one would rarely speak of a "bounded complete poset" when meaning a "bounded cpo" (which is just a "cpo with greatest element"). Likewise, "bounded complete lattice" is almost unambiguous, since one would not state the boundedness property for complete lattices, where it is implied anyway. Also note that the empty set usually has upper bounds (if the poset is non-empty) and thus a bounded-complete poset has a least element. One may also consider the subsets of a poset which are totally ordered, i.e. the chains. If all chains have a supremum, the order is called chain complete. Again, this concept is rarely needed in the dual form.Relationships between completeness properties
It was already observed that binary meets/joins yield all non-empty finite meets/joins. Likewise, many other (combinations) of the above conditions are equivalent. * The best-known example is the existence of all suprema, which is in fact equivalent to the existence of all infima. Indeed, for any subset ''X'' of a poset, one can consider its set of lower bounds ''B''. The supremum of ''B'' is then equal to the infimum of ''X'': since each element of ''X'' is an upper bound of ''B'', sup ''B'' is smaller than all elements of ''X'', i.e. sup ''B'' is in ''B''. It is the greatest element of ''B'' and hence the infimum of ''X''. In a dual way, the existence of all infima implies the existence of all suprema. * Bounded completeness can also be characterized differently. By an argument similar to the above, one finds that the supremum of a set with upper bounds is the infimum of the set of upper bounds. Consequently, bounded completeness is equivalent to the existence of all non-empty infima. * A poset is a complete lattice if and only if it is a cpo and a join-semilattice. Indeed, for any subset ''X'', the set of all finite suprema (joins) of ''X'' is directed and the supremum of this set (which exists by directed completeness) is equal to the supremum of ''X''. Thus every set has a supremum and by the above observation we have a complete lattice. The other direction of the proof is trivial. * Assuming the axiom of choice, a poset is chain complete if and only if it is a dcpo.Completeness in terms of universal algebra
As explained above, the presence of certain completeness conditions allows to regard the formation of certain suprema and infima as total operations of a partially ordered set. It turns out that in many cases it is possible to characterize completeness solely by considering appropriate algebraic structures in the sense of universal algebra, which are equipped with operations like or . By imposing additional conditions (in form of suitable identities) on these operations, one can then indeed derive the underlying partial order exclusively from such algebraic structures. Details on this characterization can be found in the articles on the "lattice-like" structures for which this is typically considered: see semilattice, lattice, Heyting algebra, and Boolean algebra. Note that the latter two structures extend the application of these principles beyond mere completeness requirements by introducing an additional operation of ''negation''.Completeness in terms of adjunctions
Another interesting way to characterize completeness properties is provided through the concept of (monotone) Galois connections, i.e. adjunctions between partial orders. In fact this approach offers additional insights both into the nature of many completeness properties and into the importance of Galois connections for order theory. The general observation on which this reformulation of completeness is based is that the construction of certain suprema or infima provides left or right adjoint parts of suitable Galois connections. Consider a partially ordered set (''X'', ≤). As a first simple example, let 1 = be a specified one-element set with the only possible partial ordering. There is an obvious mapping ''j'': ''X'' → 1 with ''j''(''x'') = * for all ''x'' in ''X''. ''X'' has a least element if and only if the function ''j'' has a lower adjoint ''j''*: 1 → ''X''. Indeed the definition for Galois connections yields that in this case ''j''*(*) ≤ ''x'' if and only if * ≤ ''j''(''x''), where the right hand side obviously holds for any ''x''. Dually, the existence of an upper adjoint for ''j'' is equivalent to ''X'' having a greatest element. Another simple mapping is the function ''q'': ''X'' → ''X'' × ''X'' given by ''q''(''x'') = (''x'', ''x''). Naturally, the intended ordering relation for ''X'' × ''X'' is just the usualSee also
* *Notes
References
* G. Markowsky and B.K. Rosen. ''Bases for chain-complete posets'' IBM Journal of Research and Development. March 1976. * Stephen Bloom. ''Varieties of ordered algebras'' Journal of Computer and System Sciences. October 1976. * Michael Smyth. ''Power domains'' Journal of Computer and System Sciences. 1978. * Daniel Lehmann. ''On the algebra of order'' Journal of Computer and System Sciences. August 1980. {{Order theory Order theory