HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In mathematical logic, the compactness theorem states that a set of first-order sentences has a model if and only if every finite
subset In mathematics, Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are ...
of it has a model. This theorem is an important tool in
model theory In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between formal theories (a collection of sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a mathematical structure), and their models (those structures in which the s ...
, as it provides a useful (but generally not effective) method for constructing models of any set of sentences that is finitely consistent. The compactness theorem for the propositional calculus is a consequence of Tychonoff's theorem (which says that the product of compact spaces is compact) applied to compact Stone spaces, hence the theorem's name. Likewise, it is analogous to the finite intersection property characterization of compactness in topological spaces: a collection of
closed set In geometry, topology, and related branches of mathematics, a closed set is a set whose complement is an open set. In a topological space, a closed set can be defined as a set which contains all its limit points. In a complete metric space, a cl ...
s in a compact space has a non-empty
intersection In mathematics, the intersection of two or more objects is another object consisting of everything that is contained in all of the objects simultaneously. For example, in Euclidean geometry, when two lines in a plane are not parallel, their i ...
if every finite subcollection has a non-empty intersection. The compactness theorem is one of the two key properties, along with the downward
Löwenheim–Skolem theorem In mathematical logic, the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem is a theorem on the existence and cardinality of models, named after Leopold Löwenheim and Thoralf Skolem. The precise formulation is given below. It implies that if a countable first-order t ...
, that is used in Lindström's theorem to characterize first-order logic. Although there are some generalizations of the compactness theorem to non-first-order logics, the compactness theorem itself does not hold in them, except for a very limited number of examples.


History

Kurt Gödel Kurt Friedrich Gödel ( , ; April 28, 1906 – January 14, 1978) was a logician, mathematician, and philosopher. Considered along with Aristotle and Gottlob Frege to be one of the most significant logicians in history, Gödel had an imme ...
proved the countable compactness theorem in 1930. Anatoly Maltsev proved the uncountable case in 1936.


Applications

The compactness theorem has many applications in model theory; a few typical results are sketched here.


Robinson's principle

The compactness theorem implies the following result, stated by Abraham Robinson in his
1949 Events January * January 1 – A United Nations-sponsored ceasefire brings an end to the Indo-Pakistani War of 1947. The war results in a stalemate and the division of Kashmir, which still continues as of 2022. * January 2 – Luis ...
dissertation. Robinson's principle: If a first-order sentence holds in every field of characteristic zero, then there exists a constant p such that the sentence holds for every field of characteristic larger than p. This can be seen as follows: suppose \varphi is a sentence that holds in every field of characteristic zero. Then its negation \lnot \varphi, together with the field axioms and the infinite sequence of sentences 1 + 1 \neq 0, \;\; 1 + 1 + 1 \neq 0, \; \ldots is not satisfiable (because there is no field of characteristic 0 in which \lnot \varphi holds, and the infinite sequence of sentences ensures any model would be a field of characteristic 0). Therefore, there is a finite subset A of these sentences that is not satisfiable. A must contain \lnot \varphi because otherwise it would be satisfiable. Because adding more sentences to A does not change unsatisfiability, we can assume that A contains the field axioms and, for some k, the first k sentences of the form 1 + 1 + \cdots + 1 \neq 0. Let B contain all the sentences of A except \lnot \varphi. Then any field with a characteristic greater than k is a model of B, and \lnot \varphi together with B is not satisfiable. This means that \varphi must hold in every model of B, which means precisely that \varphi holds in every field of characteristic greater than k. This completes the proof. The Lefschetz principle, one of the first examples of a transfer principle, extends this result. A first-order sentence \varphi in the language of rings is true in (or equivalently, in ) algebraically closed field of characteristic 0 (such as the complex numbers for instance) if and only if there exist infinitely many primes p for which \varphi is true in algebraically closed field of characteristic p, in which case \varphi is true in algebraically closed fields of sufficiently large non-0 characteristic p. One consequence is the following special case of the
Ax–Grothendieck theorem In mathematics, the Ax–Grothendieck theorem is a result about injectivity and surjectivity of polynomials that was proved independently by James Ax and Alexander Grothendieck. The theorem is often given as this special case: If ''P'' is an injec ...
: all
injective In mathematics, an injective function (also known as injection, or one-to-one function) is a function that maps distinct elements of its domain to distinct elements; that is, implies . (Equivalently, implies in the equivalent contrapositiv ...
complex polynomials \Complex^n \to \Complex^n are
surjective In mathematics, a surjective function (also known as surjection, or onto function) is a function that every element can be mapped from element so that . In other words, every element of the function's codomain is the image of one element of i ...
(indeed, it can even be shown that its inverse will also be a polynomial). In fact, the surjectivity conclusion remains true for any injective polynomial F^n \to F^n where F is a finite field or the algebraic closure of such a field.


Upward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem

A second application of the compactness theorem shows that any theory that has arbitrarily large finite models, or a single infinite model, has models of arbitrary large
cardinality In mathematics, the cardinality of a set is a measure of the number of elements of the set. For example, the set A = \ contains 3 elements, and therefore A has a cardinality of 3. Beginning in the late 19th century, this concept was generalized ...
(this is the
Upward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem Upward may refer to: Music * ''Upwards'' (album), a 2003 album British hip-hop artist Ty Organizations * Upward Bound, a federally funded educational program within the United States * Upward Bound High School, a school in Hartwick, New York * ...
). So for instance, there are nonstandard models of
Peano arithmetic In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly u ...
with uncountably many 'natural numbers'. To achieve this, let T be the initial theory and let \kappa be any cardinal number. Add to the language of T one constant symbol for every element of \kappa. Then add to T a collection of sentences that say that the objects denoted by any two distinct constant symbols from the new collection are distinct (this is a collection of \kappa^2 sentences). Since every subset of this new theory is satisfiable by a sufficiently large finite model of T, or by any infinite model, the entire extended theory is satisfiable. But any model of the extended theory has cardinality at least \kappa.


Non-standard analysis

A third application of the compactness theorem is the construction of nonstandard models of the real numbers, that is, consistent extensions of the theory of the real numbers that contain "infinitesimal" numbers. To see this, let \Sigma be a first-order axiomatization of the theory of the real numbers. Consider the theory obtained by adding a new constant symbol \varepsilon to the language and adjoining to \Sigma the axiom \varepsilon > 0 and the axioms \varepsilon < \tfrac for all positive integers n. Clearly, the standard real numbers \R are a model for every finite subset of these axioms, because the real numbers satisfy everything in \Sigma and, by suitable choice of \varepsilon, can be made to satisfy any finite subset of the axioms about \varepsilon. By the compactness theorem, there is a model ^* \R that satisfies \Sigma and also contains an infinitesimal element \varepsilon. A similar argument, this time adjoining the axioms \omega > 0, \; \omega > 1, \ldots, etc., shows that the existence of numbers with infinitely large magnitudes cannot be ruled out by any axiomatization \Sigma of the reals. It can be shown that the hyperreal numbers ^* \R satisfy the transfer principle: a first-order sentence is true of \R if and only if it is true of ^* \R.


Proofs

One can prove the compactness theorem using Gödel's completeness theorem, which establishes that a set of sentences is satisfiable if and only if no contradiction can be proven from it. Since proofs are always finite and therefore involve only finitely many of the given sentences, the compactness theorem follows. In fact, the compactness theorem is equivalent to Gödel's completeness theorem, and both are equivalent to the Boolean prime ideal theorem, a weak form of the axiom of choice.See Hodges (1993). Gödel originally proved the compactness theorem in just this way, but later some "purely semantic" proofs of the compactness theorem were found; that is, proofs that refer to but not to . One of those proofs relies on ultraproducts hinging on the axiom of choice as follows: Proof: Fix a first-order language L, and let \Sigma be a collection of L-sentences such that every finite subcollection of L-sentences, i \subseteq \Sigma of it has a model \mathcal_i. Also let \prod_\mathcal_i be the direct product of the structures and I be the collection of finite subsets of \Sigma. For each i \in I, let A_i = \. The family of all of these sets A_i generates a proper filter, so there is an ultrafilter U containing all sets of the form A_i. Now for any formula \varphi in \Sigma: * the set A_ is in U * whenever j \in A_, then \varphi \in j, hence \varphi holds in \mathcal M_j * the set of all j with the property that \varphi holds in \mathcal M_j is a superset of A_, hence also in U Łoś's theorem now implies that \varphi holds in the ultraproduct \prod_ \mathcal_i/U. So this ultraproduct satisfies all formulas in \Sigma.


See also

* * * *


Notes


References

* * * * * * * * *


External links


Compactness Theorem
''
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy The ''Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (''IEP'') is a scholarly online encyclopedia, dealing with philosophy, philosophical topics, and philosophers. The IEP combines open access publication with peer reviewed publication of original pape ...
''. {{Mathematical logic Mathematical logic Metatheorems Model theory Theorems in the foundations of mathematics