HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Abu Nasr Muhammad Al-Farabi ( fa, ابونصر محمد فارابی), ( ar, أبو نصر محمد الفارابي), known in the West as Alpharabius; (c. 872 – between 14 December, 950 and 12 January, 951)
PDF version
was a renowned early Islamic philosopher and
jurist A jurist is a person with expert knowledge of law; someone who analyses and comments on law. This person is usually a specialist legal scholar, mostly (but not always) with a formal qualification in law and often a legal practitioner. In the Uni ...
who wrote in the fields of political philosophy, metaphysics, ethics and logic. He was also a scientist, cosmologist, mathematician and music theorist. Ludwig W. Adamec (2009), ''Historical Dictionary of Islam'', pp.95–96. Scarecrow Press. . In Islamic philosophical tradition he was often called "the Second Teacher", following
Aristotle Aristotle (; grc-gre, Ἀριστοτέλης ''Aristotélēs'', ; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and polymath during the Classical Greece, Classical period in Ancient Greece. Taught by Plato, he was the founder of the Peripatet ...
who was known as "the First Teacher". He is credited with preserving the original Greek texts during the Middle Ages via his commentaries and treatises, and influencing many prominent philosophers, such as
Avicenna Ibn Sina ( fa, ابن سینا; 980 – June 1037 CE), commonly known in the West as Avicenna (), was a Persian polymath who is regarded as one of the most significant physicians, astronomers, philosophers, and writers of the Islamic G ...
and Maimonides. Through his works, he became well-known in the West as well as the East.


Biography

The existing variations in the basic accounts of al-Farabi's origins and pedigree indicate that they were not recorded during his lifetime or soon thereafter by anyone with concrete information, but were based on hearsay or guesses (as is the case with other contemporaries of al-Farabi). Little is known about his life. Early sources include an autobiographical passage where al-Farabi traces the history of logic and philosophy up to his time, and brief mentions by Al-Masudi, Ibn al-Nadim and Ibn Hawqal. Said Al-Andalusi wrote a biography of al-Farabi.
Arabic Arabic (, ' ; , ' or ) is a Semitic language spoken primarily across the Arab world.Semitic languages: an international handbook / edited by Stefan Weninger; in collaboration with Geoffrey Khan, Michael P. Streck, Janet C. E.Watson; Walte ...
biographers of the 12th–13th centuries thus had few facts to hand, and used invented stories about his life. From incidental accounts it is known that he spent significant time (most of his life) in Baghdad with Christian scholars including the cleric Yuhanna ibn Haylan, Yahya ibn Adi, and Abu Ishaq Ibrahim al-Baghdadi. He later spent time in
Damascus )), is an adjective which means "spacious". , motto = , image_flag = Flag of Damascus.svg , image_seal = Emblem of Damascus.svg , seal_type = Seal , map_caption = , ...
and in Egypt before returning to Damascus where he died in 950-1. His name was Abū Naṣr Muḥammad b. Muḥammad Farabi, sometimes with the family surname al-Ṭarḵānī, i.e., the element Ṭarḵān appears in a nisba. His grandfather was not known among his contemporaries, but a name, Awzalaḡ, suddenly appears later in the writings of Ibn Abī Uṣaibiʿa, and of his great-grandfather in those of Ibn Khallikan. His birthplace could have been any one of the many places in Central Asia- then known by the name of
Khurasan Greater Khorāsān,Dabeersiaghi, Commentary on Safarnâma-e Nâsir Khusraw, 6th Ed. Tehran, Zavvâr: 1375 (Solar Hijri Calendar) 235–236 or Khorāsān ( pal, Xwarāsān; fa, خراسان ), is a historical eastern region in the Iranian Plate ...
. The name "parab/farab" is a Persian term for a locale that is irrigated by effluent springs or flows from a nearby river. Thus, there are many places that carry the name (or various evolutions of that hydrological/geological toponym) in that general area, such as Fārāb on the Jaxartes (
Syr Darya The Syr Darya (, ),, , ; rus, Сырдарья́, Syrdarjja, p=sɨrdɐˈrʲja; fa, سيردريا, Sirdaryâ; tg, Сирдарё, Sirdaryo; tr, Seyhun, Siri Derya; ar, سيحون, Seyḥūn; uz, Sirdaryo, script-Latn/. historically known ...
) in modern Kazakhstan, Fārāb, an still-extant village in suburbs of the city of Chaharjuy/Amol (modern Türkmenabat) on the Oxus Amu Darya in Turkmenistan, on the
Silk Road The Silk Road () was a network of Eurasian trade routes active from the second century BCE until the mid-15th century. Spanning over 6,400 kilometers (4,000 miles), it played a central role in facilitating economic, cultural, political, and reli ...
, connecting Merv to
Bukhara Bukhara (Uzbek language, Uzbek: /, ; tg, Бухоро, ) is the List of cities in Uzbekistan, seventh-largest city in Uzbekistan, with a population of 280,187 , and the capital of Bukhara Region. People have inhabited the region around Bukhara ...
, or Fāryāb in Greater Khorasan (modern day Afghanistan). The older Persian Pārāb (in Ḥudūd al-ʿĀlam) or Fāryāb (also Pāryāb), is a common Persian toponym meaning "lands irrigated by diversion of river water". By the 13th century, Fārāb on the Jaxartes was known as Otrār.


Background

While Scholars largely agree that his ethnic background is not knowable, Al-Farabi has also been described as being of either Persian or Turkic origin. Medieval Arab historian Ibn Abī Uṣaibiʿa (died in 1270)—al-Farabi's oldest biographer—mentions in his ʿUyūn that al-Farabi's father was of Persian descent. Al-Shahrazūrī who lived around 1288 and has written an early biography also states that Farabi hailed from a Persian family.Seyyed Hossein Nasr, Mehdi Amin Razavi. "An Anthology of Philosophy in Persia, Vol. 1: From Zoroaster to Umar Khayyam", I.B. Tauris in association with The Institute of Ismaili Studies, 2007. Pg 134: "Ibn Nadim in his al-Fihrist, which is the first work to mention Farabi considers him to be of Persian origin, as does Muhammad Shahrazuri in his ''Tarikh al-hukama'' and Ibn Abi Usaybi'ah in his ''Tabaqat al-atibba''. In contrast, Ibn Khallikan in his '"Wafayat al-'ayan considers him to be of Turkish descent. In any case, he was born in Farab in Khurasan of that day around 257/870 in a climate of Persianate culture" According to Majid Fakhry, an Emeritus Professor of Philosophy at Georgetown University, Farabi's father "''was an army captain of Persian extraction.''" A Persian origin has been stated by many other sources as well. Dimitri Gutas notes that Farabi's works contain references and glosses in Persian, Sogdian, and even Greek, but not Turkish. Sogdian has also been suggested as his native language and the language of the inhabitants of Fārāb. Muhammad Javad Mashkoor argues for an Iranian-speaking Central Asian origin.مشكور، محمدجواد. “فاراب و فارابي“. دوره14، ش161 (اسفند 54): 15-20- . J. Mashkur, "Farabi and Farabi" in volume 14, No. 161, pp 15–12, Tehran,1972

English translations of the arguments used by J. Mashkur can be found in: G. Lohraspi, "Some remarks on Farabi's background"; a scholarly approach citing Clifford Edmund Bosworth, C.E. Bosworth, B. Lewis, R. Frye, D. Gutas, J. Mashkur and partial translation of J.Mashkur's arguments
PDF
ولي فارابي فيلسوف تنها متعلق به ايران نبود بلكه به عالم اسلام تعلق داشت و از بركت قرآن و دين محمد به اين مقام رسيد. از اينجهت هه دانشمنداني كه در اينجا گرد آمده‌اند او را يك دانشمند مسلمان متعلق به عالم انسانيت مي‌دانند و كاري به تركي و فارسي و عربي بودن او ندارند.
According to Christoph Baumer, he was probably a
Sogdia Sogdia (Sogdian language, Sogdian: ) or Sogdiana was an ancient Iranian peoples, Iranian civilization between the Amu Darya and the Syr Darya, and in present-day Uzbekistan, Turkmenistan, Tajikistan, Kazakhstan, and Kyrgyzstan. Sogdiana was also ...
n. According to Therese-Anne Druart, writing in 2020, "Scholars have disputed his ethnic origin. Some claimed he was Turkish but more recent research points to him being a Persian." The oldest known reference to a
Turkic Turkic may refer to: * anything related to the country of Turkey * Turkic languages, a language family of at least thirty-five documented languages ** Turkic alphabets (disambiguation) ** Turkish language, the most widely spoken Turkic language * ...
origin is given by the medieval historian Ibn Khallikān (died in 1282), who in his work ''Wafayāt'' (completed in 669/1271) states that Farabi was born in the small village of
Wasij Wasij was a village near Farab in Kazakhstan and the birthplace of the Central Asian scientist Al-Farabi Abu Nasr Muhammad Al-Farabi ( fa, ابونصر محمد فارابی), ( ar, أبو نصر محمد الفارابي), known in the Western ...
near Fārāb (in what is today Otrar, Kazakhstan) of Turkic parents. Based on this account, some scholars say he is of Turkic origin. Dimitri Gutas, an American Arabist of Greek origin, criticizes this, saying that Ibn Khallikān's account is aimed at the earlier historical accounts by Ibn Abī Uṣaibiʿa, and serves the purpose to "prove" a Turkic origin for al-Farabi, for instance by mentioning the additional nisba (surname) ''"al-Turk"'' (arab. "the Turk")—a nisba Farabi never had. However,
Abu al-Fedā' Ismāʿīl b. ʿAlī b. Maḥmūd b. Muḥammad b. ʿUmar b. Shāhanshāh b. Ayyūb b. Shādī b. Marwān ( ar, إسماعيل بن علي بن محمود بن محمد بن عمر بن شاهنشاه بن أيوب بن شادي بن مروان ...
, who copied Ibn Ḵhallekān, corrected this and changed ''al-Torkī'' to the phrase "wa-kāna rajolan torkīyan", meaning "he was a Turkish man." In this regard, since works of such supposed Turks lack traces of Turkic nomadic culture, Oxford professor Clifford Edmund Bosworth, C.E. Bosworth notes that "great figures uchas al-Farabi, al-Biruni, and
ibn Sina Ibn Sina ( fa, ابن سینا; 980 – June 1037 CE), commonly known in the West as Avicenna (), was a Persian polymath who is regarded as one of the most significant physicians, astronomers, philosophers, and writers of the Islamic G ...
have been attached by over enthusiastic Turkish scholars to their race". R.N. Freye and Aydin Sayili on the other hand assert, that Turks lived long before the Seljuks in Transoxiana during the Arab conquest in villages and these Turks had no nomadic life.


Life and education

Al-Farabi spent almost his entire life in Baghdad. In the auto-biographical passage preserved by Ibn Abī Uṣaibiʿa, Farabi stated that he had studied logic, medicine and sociology with Yūḥannā bin Ḥaylān up to and including Aristotle's ''
Posterior Analytics The ''Posterior Analytics'' ( grc-gre, Ἀναλυτικὰ Ὕστερα; la, Analytica Posteriora) is a text from Aristotle's ''Organon'' that deals with demonstration, definition, and scientific knowledge. The demonstration is distinguished ...
'', i.e., according to the order of the books studied in the curriculum, Fārābī was claiming that he had studied Porphyry's ''Eisagoge'' and Aristotle's ''Categories'', ''De Interpretatione'', ''Prior and Posterior Analytics''. His teacher, bin Ḥaylān, was a Nestorian cleric. This period of study was probably in Baghdad, where Al-Masudi records that Yūḥannā died during the reign of
Al-Muqtadir Abu’l-Faḍl Jaʿfar ibn Ahmad al-Muʿtaḍid ( ar, أبو الفضل جعفر بن أحمد المعتضد) (895 – 31 October 932 AD), better known by his regnal name Al-Muqtadir bi-llāh ( ar, المقتدر بالله, "Mighty in God"), wa ...
(295-320/908-32). He was in Baghdad at least until the end of September 942, as recorded in notes in his ''Mabādeʾ ārāʾ ahl al-madīna al-fāżela''. He finished the book in Damascus the following year (331), i.e., by September 943). He also studied in Tétouan, Morocco and lived and taught for some time in
Aleppo )), is an adjective which means "white-colored mixed with black". , motto = , image_map = , mapsize = , map_caption = , image_map1 = ...
. Farabi later visited Egypt, finishing six sections summarizing the book ''Mabādeʾ'' in Egypt in 337/July 948 – June 949 when he returned to Syria, where he was supported by Sayf al-Dawla, the Hamdanid ruler. Al-Masudi, writing barely five years after the fact (955-6, the date of the composition of the Tanbīh), says that Farabi died in
Damascus )), is an adjective which means "spacious". , motto = , image_flag = Flag of Damascus.svg , image_seal = Emblem of Damascus.svg , seal_type = Seal , map_caption = , ...
in Rajab 339 (between 14 December 950 and 12 January 951).


Religious beliefs

Al-Farabi's religious affiliation within Islam is disputed. While some historians identify him as
Sunni Sunni Islam () is the largest branch of Islam, followed by 85–90% of the world's Muslims. Its name comes from the word '' Sunnah'', referring to the tradition of Muhammad. The differences between Sunni and Shia Muslims arose from a disagr ...
, some others assert he was Shia or influenced by Shia. Najjar Fauzi argues that al-Farabi's political philosophy was influenced by Shiite sects. Giving a positive account,
Nadia Maftouni Nadia Maftouni ( fa, نادیا مفتونی, born 14 January 1966) is an Iranian academic, philosophical author and artist. She is best known as a leading Researcher on Farabian, Avicennian and Suhrawardian philosophy with her modern reading ...
describes shi'ite aspects of Farabi's writings. As she put it, Farabi in his Al-Millah, Al-Sīyāsah al-Madanīyah, and Tahsil al-Sa’adah believes in a utopia governed by prophet and his successors: the Imams.


Works and contributions

Farabi made contributions to the fields of logic,
mathematics Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics ...
, music,
philosophy Philosophy (from , ) is the systematized study of general and fundamental questions, such as those about existence, reason, knowledge, values, mind, and language. Such questions are often posed as problems to be studied or resolved. Some ...
, psychology, and education.


Alchemy

Al-Farabi wrote: ''The Necessity of the Art of the Elixir''


Logic

Though he was mainly an Aristotelian logician, he included a number of non-Aristotelian elements in his works. He discussed the topics of future contingents, the number and relation of the categories, the relation between logic and grammar, and non-Aristotelian forms of
inference Inferences are steps in reasoning, moving from premises to logical consequences; etymologically, the word '' infer'' means to "carry forward". Inference is theoretically traditionally divided into deduction and induction, a distinction that in ...
. He is also credited with categorizing logic into two separate groups, the first being "idea" and the second being "
proof Proof most often refers to: * Proof (truth), argument or sufficient evidence for the truth of a proposition * Alcohol proof, a measure of an alcoholic drink's strength Proof may also refer to: Mathematics and formal logic * Formal proof, a con ...
". Al-Farabi also considered the theories of conditional syllogisms and analogical inference, which were part of the Stoic tradition of logic rather than the Aristotelian. Another addition al-Farabi made to the Aristotelian tradition was his introduction of the concept of poetic syllogism in a commentary on Aristotle's ''
Poetics Poetics is the theory of structure, form, and discourse within literature, and, in particular, within poetry. History The term ''poetics'' derives from the Ancient Greek ποιητικός ''poietikos'' "pertaining to poetry"; also "creative" an ...
''.


Music

Al-Farabi wrote a book on music titled ''
Kitab al-Musiqa ''Kitab al-Musiqa al-Kabir'' ( ar, كتاب الموسيقى الكبير, en, the Great Book of Music) is a treatise on music in east by the medieval philosopher al-Farabi (872-950/951). The work prescribes different aspects of music such as ma ...
'' (The Book of Music). In it, he presents philosophical principles about music, its cosmic qualities, and its influences. He also wrote a treatise on the ''Meanings of the Intellect'', which dealt with music therapy and discussed the therapeutic effects of music on the soul.


Philosophy

As a philosopher, Al-Farabi was a founder of his own school of
early Islamic philosophy Early Islamic philosophy or classical Islamic philosophy is a period of intense philosophical development beginning in the 2nd century AH of the Islamic calendar (early 9th century CE) and lasting until the 6th century AH (late 12th century CE) ...
known as "Farabism" or "Alfarabism", though it was later overshadowed by Avicennism. Al-Farabi's school of philosophy "breaks with the philosophy of Plato and
Aristotle Aristotle (; grc-gre, Ἀριστοτέλης ''Aristotélēs'', ; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and polymath during the Classical Greece, Classical period in Ancient Greece. Taught by Plato, he was the founder of the Peripatet ...
[... and ...] moves from Islamic metaphysics, metaphysics to Scientific method, methodology, a move that anticipates modernity", and "at the level of philosophy, Alfarabi unites theory and practice [... and] in the sphere of the Politics, political he liberates practice from theory". His Neoplatonism, Neoplatonic theology is also more than just metaphysics as rhetoric. In his attempt to think through the nature of a Primum movens, First Cause, Alfarabi discovers the limits of human knowledge". Al-Farabi had great influence on science and philosophy for several centuries, and was widely considered second only to Aristotle in knowledge (alluded to by his title of "the Second Teacher") in his time. His work, aimed at synthesis of philosophy and Sufism, paved the way for the work of Avicenna, Ibn Sina (Avicenna). Al-Farabi also wrote a commentary on
Aristotle Aristotle (; grc-gre, Ἀριστοτέλης ''Aristotélēs'', ; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and polymath during the Classical Greece, Classical period in Ancient Greece. Taught by Plato, he was the founder of the Peripatet ...
's work, and one of his most notable works is ''Al-Madina al-Fadila'' () where he theorized an ideal Sovereign state, state as in Plato's ''The Republic (Plato), The Republic''.Arabic and Islamic Natural Philosophy and Natural Science
''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy''
Al-Farabi argued that religion rendered truth through symbols and persuasion, and, like Plato, saw it as the duty of the philosopher to provide guidance to the state. Al-Farabi incorporated the Platonism, Platonic view, drawing a parallel from within the Islamic context, in that he regarded the ideal state to be ruled by the Prophets of Islam, prophet-imam, instead of the philosopher-king envisaged by Plato. Al-Farabi argued that the ideal state was the city-state of Medina when it was governed by the prophet Muhammad as its head of state, as he was in direct communion with Allah whose law was revealed to him. In the absence of the prophet-imam, Al-Farabi considered democracy as the closest to the ideal state, regarding the republican order of the Sunni Rashidun Caliphate as an example within early Muslim history. However, he also maintained that it was from democracy that imperfect states emerged, noting how the republican order of the early Islamic Caliphate of the Rashidun caliphs was later replaced by a form of government resembling a monarchy under the Umayyad and Abbasid dynasties.


Physics

Al-Farabi wrote a short treatise "On Vacuum", where he thought about the nature of the existence of vacuum, void. His final conclusion was that air's volume can expand to fill available space, and he suggested that the concept of perfect vacuum was incoherent.


Psychology

Al-Farabi wrote ''Social Psychology'' and ''Principles of the Opinions of the Citizens of the Virtuous City'', which were the first treatises to deal with social psychology. He stated that "an isolated individual could not achieve all the perfections by himself, without the aid of other individuals," and that it is the "innate disposition of every human being to join another human being or other men in the labor he ought to perform." He concluded that to "achieve what he can of that perfection, every man needs to stay in the neighborhood of others and associate with them."Amber Haque (2004), "Psychology from Islamic Perspective: Contributions of Early Muslim Scholars and Challenges to Contemporary Muslim Psychologists", ''Journal of Religion and Health'' 43 (4): 357–377 [363]. In his treatise ''On the Cause of Dreams'', which appeared as chapter 24 of his ''Principles of the Opinions of the Citizens of the Ideal City'', he distinguished between dream interpretation and the nature and causes of dreams.


Philosophical thought


Influences

The main influence on al-Farabi's philosophy was the Aristotelianism, Aristotelian tradition of Alexandria. A prolific writer, he is credited with over one hundred works. Amongst these are a number of prolegomena to philosophy, commentaries on important Aristotelian works (such as the Nicomachean Ethics) as well as his own works. His ideas are marked by their coherency, despite drawing together of many different philosophical disciplines and traditions. Some other significant influences on his work were the planetary model of Ptolemy and elements of Neo-Platonism, particularly metaphysics and practical (or political) philosophy (which bears more resemblance to Plato's ''Republic'' than Aristotle's ''Politics'').


Al-Farabi, Aristotle, Maimonides

In the handing down of Aristotle’s thought to the Christian west in the middle ages, al-Farabi played an essential part as appears in the translation of Farabi’s ''Commentary and Short Treatise on Aristotle’s de Interpretatione'' that F.W. Zimmermann published in 1981. Farabi had a great influence on Maimonides, the most important Jewish thinker of the middle ages. Maimonides wrote in Arabic a ''Treatise on logic'', the celebrated ''Maqala fi sina at al-mantiq''. In a wonderfully concise way, the work treats of the essentials of Aristotelian logic in the light of comments made by the Persian philosophers:
Avicenna Ibn Sina ( fa, ابن سینا; 980 – June 1037 CE), commonly known in the West as Avicenna (), was a Persian polymath who is regarded as one of the most significant physicians, astronomers, philosophers, and writers of the Islamic G ...
and, above all, al-Farabi. Rémi Brague in his book devoted to the Treatise stresses the fact that Farabi is the only thinker mentioned therein. Al-Farabi as well as Ibn Sina and Averroes have been recognized as Peripatetics (''al-Mashsha’iyu''n) or Rationalism, rationalists (''Estedlaliun'') among Muslims. However, he tried to gather the ideas of Plato and
Aristotle Aristotle (; grc-gre, Ἀριστοτέλης ''Aristotélēs'', ; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and polymath during the Classical Greece, Classical period in Ancient Greece. Taught by Plato, he was the founder of the Peripatet ...
in his book "The gathering of the ideas of the two philosophers". According to Adamson, his work was singularly directed towards the goal of simultaneously reviving and reinventing the Alexandrian philosophical tradition, to which his Christian teacher, Yuhanna bin Haylan belonged. His success should be measured by the honorific title of "the second master" of philosophy (Aristotle being the first), by which he was known. Adamson also says that he does not make any reference to the ideas of either al-Kindi or his contemporary, Abu Bakr al-Razi, which clearly indicates that he did not consider their approach to Philosophy as a correct or viable one.


Thought


Metaphysics and cosmology

In contrast to al-Kindi, who considered the subject of metaphysics to be God, al-Farabi believed that it was concerned primarily with being ''qua'' being (that is, being in and of itself), and this is related to God only to the extent that God is a principle of absolute being. Al-Kindi's view was, however, a common misconception regarding Greek philosophy amongst Muslim intellectuals at the time, and it was for this reason that
Avicenna Ibn Sina ( fa, ابن سینا; 980 – June 1037 CE), commonly known in the West as Avicenna (), was a Persian polymath who is regarded as one of the most significant physicians, astronomers, philosophers, and writers of the Islamic G ...
remarked that he did not understand Aristotle's ''Metaphysics'' properly until he had read a prolegomenon written by al-Farabi. Al-Farabi's cosmology is essentially based upon three pillars: Aristotelian metaphysics of causation, highly developed Plotinus, Plotinian emanationism, emanational cosmology and the Ptolemaic astronomy. In his model, the universe is viewed as a number of concentric circles; the outermost sphere or "first heaven", the sphere of fixed stars, Saturn, Jupiter, Mars, the Sun, Venus, Mercury and finally, the Moon. At the centre of these concentric circles is the sub-lunar realm which contains the material world.Black, p189 Each of these circles represent the domain of the secondary intelligences (symbolized by the celestial bodies themselves), which act as causal intermediaries between the First Cause (in this case, God) and the material world. Furthermore these are said to have emanated from God, who is both their formal and efficient cause. The process of emanation begins (metaphysically, not temporally) with the First Cause, whose principal activity is self-contemplation. And it is this intellectual activity that underlies its role in the creation of the universe. The First Cause, by thinking of itself, "overflows" and the incorporeal entity of the second intellect "emanates" from it. Like its predecessor, the second intellect also thinks about itself, and thereby brings its celestial sphere (in this case, the sphere of fixed stars) into being, but in addition to this it must also contemplate upon the First Cause, and this causes the "emanation" of the next intellect. The cascade of emanation continues until it reaches the tenth intellect, beneath which is the material world. And as each intellect must contemplate both itself and an increasing number of predecessors, each succeeding level of existence becomes more and more complex. This process is based upon necessity as opposed to will. In other words, God does not have a choice whether or not to create the universe, but by virtue of His own existence, He causes it to be. This view also suggests that the universe is eternal, and both of these points were criticized by al-Ghazzali in his attack on the philosophers In his discussion of the First Cause (or God), al-Farabi relies heavily on negative theology. He says that it cannot be known by intellectual means, such as dialectical division or definition, because the terms used in these processes to define a thing constitute its substance. Therefore if one was to define the First Cause, each of the terms used would actually constitute a ''part'' of its substance and therefore behave as a ''cause'' for its existence, which is impossible as the First Cause is uncaused; it exists without being caused. Equally, he says it cannot be known according to genus and differentia, as its substance and existence are different from all others, and therefore it has no category to which it belongs. If this were the case, then it would not be the First Cause, because something would be prior in existence to it, which is also impossible. This would suggest that the more philosophically simple a thing is, the more perfect it is. And based on this observation, Adamson says it is possible to see the entire hierarchy of al-Farabi's cosmology according to classification into genus and species. Each succeeding level in this structure has as its principal qualities multiplicity and deficiency, and it is this ever-increasing complexity that typifies the material world.


Epistemology and eschatology

Human beings are unique in al-Farabi's vision of the universe because they stand between two worlds: the "higher", immaterial world of the celestial intellects and universal intelligibles, and the "lower", material world of generation and decay; they inhabit a physical body, and so belong to the "lower" world, but they also have a rational capacity, which connects them to the "higher" realm. Each level of existence in al-Farabi's cosmology is characterized by its movement towards perfection, which is to become like the First Cause, i.e. a perfect intellect. Human perfection (or "happiness"), then, is equated with constant intellection and contemplation. Al-Farabi divides intellect into four categories: potential, actual, acquired and the Agent. The first three are the different states of the human intellect and the fourth is the Tenth Intellect (the moon) in his emanational cosmology. The potential intellect represents the capacity to think, which is shared by all human beings, and the actual intellect is an intellect engaged in the act of thinking. By thinking, al-Farabi means abstracting universal intelligibles from the sensory forms of objects which have been apprehended and retained in the individual's imagination. This motion from potentiality to actuality requires the Agent Intellect to act upon the retained sensory forms; just as the Sun illuminates the physical world to allow us to see, the Agent Intellect illuminates the world of intelligibles to allow us to think.Reisman, p64 This illumination removes all accident (such as time, place, quality) and physicality from them, converting them into primary intelligibles, which are logical principles such as "the whole is greater than the part". The human intellect, by its act of intellection, passes from potentiality to actuality, and as it gradually comprehends these intelligibles, it is identified with them (as according to Aristotle, by knowing something, the intellect becomes like it).Reisman, p63 Because the Agent Intellect knows all of the intelligibles, this means that when the human intellect knows all of them, it becomes associated with the Agent Intellect's perfection and is known as the acquired Intellect.Black, p186 While this process seems mechanical, leaving little room for human choice or volition, Reisman says that al-Farabi is committed to human voluntarism. This takes place when man, based on the knowledge he has acquired, decides whether to direct himself towards virtuous or unvirtuous activities, and thereby decides whether or not to seek true happiness. And it is by choosing what is ethical and contemplating about what constitutes the nature of ethics, that the actual intellect can become "like" the active intellect, thereby attaining perfection. It is only by this process that a human soul may survive death, and live on in the afterlife. According to al-Farabi, the afterlife is not the personal experience commonly conceived of by religious traditions such as Islam and Christianity. Any individual or distinguishing features of the soul are annihilated after the death of the body; only the rational faculty survives (and then, only if it has attained perfection), which becomes one with all other rational souls within the agent intellect and enters a realm of pure intelligence. Henry Corbin compares this eschatology with that of the Ismaili Neo-Platonists, for whom this process initiated the next grand cycle of the universe. However, Deborah Black mentions we have cause to be skeptical as to whether this was the mature and developed view of al-Farabi, as later thinkers such as Ibn Tufayl, Averroes and Ibn Bajjah would assert that he repudiated this view in his commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics, which has been lost to modern experts.


Psychology, the soul and prophetic knowledge

In his treatment of the human soul, al-Farabi draws on a basic Aristotelian outline, which is informed by the commentaries of later Greek thinkers. He says it is composed of four faculties: The ''appetitive'' (the desire for, or aversion to an object of sense), the ''sensitive'' (the perception by the senses of corporeal substances), the ''imaginative'' (the faculty which retains images of sensible objects after they have been perceived, and then separates and combines them for a number of ends), and the ''rational'', which is the faculty of intellection. It is the last of these which is unique to human beings and distinguishes them from plants and animals. It is also the only part of the soul to survive the death of the body. Noticeably absent from these scheme are internal senses, such as common sense, which would be discussed by later philosophers such as
Avicenna Ibn Sina ( fa, ابن سینا; 980 – June 1037 CE), commonly known in the West as Avicenna (), was a Persian polymath who is regarded as one of the most significant physicians, astronomers, philosophers, and writers of the Islamic G ...
and Averroes. Special attention must be given to al-Farabi's treatment of the soul's ''imaginative'' faculty, which is essential to his interpretation of prophethood and prophetic knowledge. In addition to its ability to retain and manipulate sensible images of objects, he gives the imagination the function of imitation. By this he means the capacity to represent an object with an image other than its own. In other words, to imitate "x" is to imagine "x" by associating it with sensible qualities that do not describe its own appearance. This extends the representative ability of the imagination beyond sensible forms and to include temperaments, emotions, desires and even immaterial intelligibles or abstract universals, as happens when, for example, one associates "evil" with "darkness". The prophet, in addition to his own intellectual capacity, has a very strong imaginative faculty, which allows him to receive an overflow of intelligibles from the agent intellect (the tenth intellect in the emanational cosmology). These intelligibles are then associated with symbols and images, which allow him to communicate abstract truths in a way that can be understood by ordinary people. Therefore what makes prophetic knowledge unique is not its content, which is also accessible to philosophers through demonstration and intellection, but rather the form that it is given by the prophet's imagination.


Practical philosophy (ethics and politics)

The practical application of philosophy was a major concern expressed by al-Farabi in many of his works, and while the majority of his philosophical output has been influenced by Aristotelian thought, his practical philosophy was unmistakably based on that of Plato. In a similar manner to Plato's Republic, Plato's ''Republic'', al-Farabi emphasized that philosophy was both a theoretical and practical discipline; labeling those philosophers who do not apply their erudition to practical pursuits as "futile philosophers". The ideal society, he wrote, is one directed towards the realization of "true happiness" (which can be taken to mean philosophical enlightenment) and as such, the ideal philosopher must hone all the necessary arts of rhetoric and poetics to communicate abstract truths to the ordinary people, as well as having achieved enlightenment himself. Al-Farabi compared the philosopher's role in relation to society with a physician in relation to the body; the body's health is affected by the "balance of its humorism, humours" just as the city is determined by the moral habits of its people. The philosopher's duty, he wrote, was to establish a "virtuous" society by healing the souls of the people, establishing justice and guiding them towards "true happiness". Of course, al-Farabi realized that such a society was rare and required a very specific set of historical circumstances to be realized, which means very few societies could ever attain this goal. He divided those "vicious" societies, which have fallen short of the ideal "virtuous" society, into three categories: ignorant, wicked and errant. ''Ignorant'' societies have, for whatever reason, failed to comprehend the purpose of human existence, and have supplanted the pursuit of happiness for another (inferior) goal, whether this be wealth, sensual gratification or power. Al-Farabi mentions "weeds" in the virtuous society: those people who try to undermine its progress towards the true human end. The best known Arabic source for al-Farabi's political philosophy is his work titled, ''al-Madina al-fadila'' (''The Virtuous City''). Whether or not al-Farabi actually intended to outline a political programme in his writings remains a matter of dispute amongst academics. Henry Corbin, who considers al-Farabi to be a crypto-Shi'ite, says that his ideas should be understood as a "prophetic philosophy" instead of being interpreted politically. On the other hand, Charles Butterworth (philosopher), Charles Butterworth contends that nowhere in his work does al-Farabi speak of a prophet-legislator or revelation (even the word philosophy is scarcely mentioned), and the main discussion that takes place concerns the positions of "king" and "statesmen". Occupying a middle position is David Reisman, who, like Corbin, believes that al-Farabi did not want to expound a political doctrine (although he does not go so far to attribute it to Islamic Gnosticism either). He argues that al-Farabi was using different types of society as examples, in the context of an ethical discussion, to show what effect correct or incorrect thinking could have. Lastly, Joshua Parens argues that al-Farabi was slyly asserting that a pan-Islamic society could not be made, by using reason to show how many conditions (such as moral and deliberative virtue) would have to be met, thus leading the reader to conclude that humans are not fit for such a society. Some other authors such as Mykhaylo Yakubovych argue that for al-Farabi religion (''milla'') and philosophy (''falsafa'') constituted the same praxeological value (i.e. basis for ''amal al-fadhil''—"virtuous deed"), while its epistemological level (''ilm''—"knowledge") was different.


Legacy

* A large Al-Farabi Kazakh National University, Kazakh university KazNU, bears his name. There is also an Al-Farabi Library on the university grounds. * Shymkent Pedagogical Institute of Culture named after Al-Farabi (1967-1996). * In many cities of Kazakhstan there are streets named after him. * Monuments have been erected in the cities of Almaty, Alma-Ata, Shymkent and Turkestan. * In 1975, the 1100th anniversary of Al-Farabi's birth was celebrated on a large international scale in Moscow, Alma-Ata and Baghdad. * The main-belt asteroid 7057 Al-Fārābī was named in his honor. * In November 2021, a monument to Al-Farabi was unveiled in Nur-Sultan, Kazakhstan.


See also

* List of modern-day Muslim scholars of Islam * List of Muslim scientists * Tenth Intellect in Ismailism


References


Citations


Primary sources (Fārābī) in translation

; English: * ''Al-Farabi's Commentary and Short Treatise on Aristotle's De interpretatione'', Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1981. * ''Short Commentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics'', Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1963. * ''Al-Farabi on the Perfect State'', Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985. * ''Alfarabi, The Political Writings. Selected Aphorisms and Other Texts'', Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2001. * ''Alfarabi, The Political Writings, Volume II. "Political Regime" and "Summary of Plato's Laws'', Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2015. * ''Alfarabi's Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle'', translated and with an introduction by Muhsin Mahdi, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2001. * ''Fusul al-Madani: Aphorisms of the Statesman'' Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1961. * "Al-Farabi's Long Commentary on Aristotle's Categoriae in Hebrew and Arabic", In ''Studies in Arabic and Islamic Culture'', Vol. II, edited by Abrahamov, Binyamin. Ramat: Bar-Ilan University Press, 2006. * Texts translated by D. M. Dunlop: ** "The Existence and Definition of Philosophy. From an Arabic text ascribed to al-Farabi", ''Iraq'', 1951, pp. 76–93). ** "Al-Farabi's Aphorisms of the Statesman", ''Iraq'', 1952, pp. 93–117. ** "Al-Farabi's Introductory Sections on Logic", ''The Islamic Quarterly'', 1955, pp. 264–282. ** "Al-Farabi's Eisagoge", ''The Islamic Quarterly'', 1956, pp. 117–138. ** "Al-Farabi's Introductory Risalah on Logic", ''The Islamic Quarterly'', 1956, pp. 224–235. ** "Al-Farabi's Paraphrase of the Categories of Aristotle [Part 1]", ''The Islamic Quarterly'', 1957, pp. 168–197. ** "Al-Farabi's Paraphrase of the Categories of Aristotle [Part 2]", ''The Islamic Quarterly'', 1959, pp. 21–54. ; French * ''Idées des habitants de la cité vertueuse''. Translated by Karam, J. Chlala, A. Jaussen. 1949. * ''Traité des opinions des habitants de la cité idéale''. Translated by Tahani Sabri. Paris: J. Vrin, 1990. *''Le Livre du régime politique'', introduction, traduction et commentaire de Philippe Vallat, Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 2012. ; Spanish * ''Catálogo De Las Ciencias'', Madrid: Imp. de Estanislao Maestre, 1932. *''La ciudad ideal''. Translated by Manuel Alonso. Madrid: Tecnos, 1995. * "Al-Farabi: Epístola sobre los sentidos del término intelecto", ''Revista Española de filosofía medieval'', 2002, pp. 215–223. * ''El camino de la felicidad'', trad. R. Ramón Guerrero, Madrid: Ed. Trotta, 2002 * ''Obras filosóficas y políticas'', trad. R. Ramón Guerrero, Madrid: Ed. Trotta, 2008. * ''Las filosofías de Platón y Aristóteles''. Con un Apéndice: ''Sumario de las Leyes de Platón. Prólogo y Tratado primero'', traducción, introducción y notas de Rafael Ramón Guerrero, Madrid, Ápeiron Ediciones, 2017. ; Portuguese * ''A cidade excelente''. Translated by Miguel Attie Filho. São Paulo: Attie, 2019. ; German * ''Der Musterstaat''. Translated by Friedrich Dieterici. Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1895.


Secondary sources

* Deborah Black (2001). ''Al-Farabi'' in Oliver Leaman and Hossein Nasr. ''History of Islamic Philosophy''. London: Routledge. * Deborah Black (2005). ''Psychology: Soul and Intellect'' in P. Adamson and R. Taylor (2005). ''The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy'', . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. * * Charles Butterworth (philosopher), Charles Butterworth (2005). "Ethical and Political Philosophy". In P. Adamson and R. Taylor, ''The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy'', . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. * * Majid Fakhry (2002). ''Al-Farabi, Founder of Islamic Neoplatonism: His Life, Works, and Influence'', Oxford: Oneworld Publications. . Spanish translation, as: ''Alfarabi y la fundación de la filosofía política islámica'', translated by R. Ramón Guerrero. Barcelona: Herder, 2003. * Miriam Galston (2003). ''Politics and Excellence: the Political Philosophy of Alfarabi''. Princeton: Princeton University Press. * Rafael Ramón Guerrero (2003). “Apuntes biográficos de al-Fârâbî según sus vidas árabes". In ''Anaquel de Estudios Árabes'' 14:231–238. * Christoph Marcinkowski (2002). "A Biographical Note on Ibn Bajjah (Avempace) and an English Translation of his Annotations to Al-Farabi's Isagoge". ''Iqbal Review'' vol. 43, no 2 (April), pp 83–99. * Monteil Jean-François (2004). “La transmission d’Aristote par les Arabes à la chrétienté occidentale: une trouvaille relative au De Interpretatione”. ''Revista Española de Filosofia Medieval'' 11: 181–195. * Nicholas Rescher (1964). ''Al-Kindí; An Annotated Bibliography''. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. * David Reisman (2005). ''Al-Farabi and the Philosophical Curriculum'' In P. Adamson and & R. Taylor. ''The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy'', . Cambridge: Cambridge Univ*Habib Hassan Touma (1996). ''The Music of the Arabs'', ersity Press.trans. Laurie Schwartz. Portland, Oregon: Amadeus Press. * Leo Strauss (1936), "Eine vermisste Schrift Farabis", ''Monatschrift für Geschichte und Wissenschaft des Judentums'' 80:96–106. * Leo Strauss (1945). "Fārābī's Plato", In ''Louis Ginzberg Jubilee Volume'', New York: American Academy for Jewish Research, 357-93. * Leo Strauss (1959). "How Fārābī Read Plato's Laws", In Leo Strauss, ''What Is Political Philosophy and Other Studies'' Glencoe, ILL.: The Free Press. * Leo Strauss (2013). "Some Remarks on the Political Science of Maimonides and Farabi", In Kenneth Hart Green. ''Leo Strauss on Maimonides: The Complete Writings'', Chicago: University of Chicago Press.


External links

* * * * *
PDF version
*
al-Farabi at Britannica


* Review (fr) of Nicholas Rescher, Rescher's ''Al-Fârâbî : An Annotated Bibliography'' (Pitt. Univ. Press, 1962) a
Persée.fr
brief introduction by Peter J. King

* ''[http://www.wilbourhall.org/index.html#farabi al-madina al-fadila (The Virtuous City)]''. German introduction with Arabic text.
Article discussing Soghdian origin for FarabiPDF version
https://archive.org/details/SomeRemarksOnFarabisBackgroundIranicsoghdianpersianOraltaic]
ALFARABI-Trinity College

ALFARABI-Unesco

Al Farabi
{{DEFAULTSORT:Farabi Al-Farabi, 870s births 950s deaths Year of birth uncertain Year of death uncertain 10th-century philosophers Alchemists of the medieval Islamic world Arabic commentators on Aristotle Commentators on Plato Cultural critics Epistemologists Ethicists Founders of philosophical traditions Idealists Islamic mirrors for princes Islamic philosophers Logicians Medieval physicists Metaphysicians Moral philosophers 10th-century Muslim theologians Transoxanian Islamic scholars Musical theorists of the medieval Islamic world Mystics Neoplatonists Ontologists People of the Hamdanid emirate of Aleppo Iranian chemists Persian music Philosophers of culture Philosophers of ethics and morality Philosophers of history Philosophers of language Philosophers of law Philosophers of literature Philosophers of logic Philosophers of mind Philosophers of psychology Philosophers of religion Philosophers of science Political philosophers Social critics Social philosophers Sayf al-Dawla