∄
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In predicate logic, an existential quantification is a type of quantifier, a logical constant which is interpreted as "there exists", "there is at least one", or "for some". It is usually denoted by the logical operator
symbol A symbol is a mark, sign, or word that indicates, signifies, or is understood as representing an idea, object, or relationship. Symbols allow people to go beyond what is known or seen by creating linkages between otherwise very different conc ...
∃, which, when used together with a predicate variable, is called an existential quantifier ("" or "" or "). Existential quantification is distinct from universal quantification ("for all"), which asserts that the property or relation holds for ''all'' members of the domain. Some sources use the term existentialization to refer to existential quantification.


Basics

Consider a formula that states that some natural number multiplied by itself is 25. :
0·0 = 25, or 1·1 = 25, or 2·2 = 25, or 3·3 = 25, ...
This would seem to be a logical disjunction because of the repeated use of "or". However, the ellipses make this impossible to integrate and to interpret it as a disjunction in formal logic. Instead, the statement could be rephrased more formally as :
For some natural number ''n'', ''n''·''n'' = 25.
This is a single statement using existential quantification. This statement is more precise than the original one, since the phrase "and so on" does not necessarily include all natural numbers and exclude everything else. And since the domain was not stated explicitly, the phrase could not be interpreted formally. In the quantified statement, however, the natural numbers are mentioned explicitly. This particular example is true, because 5 is a natural number, and when we substitute 5 for ''n'', we produce "5·5 = 25", which is true. It does not matter that "''n''·''n'' = 25" is only true for a single natural number, 5; even the existence of a single
solution Solution may refer to: * Solution (chemistry), a mixture where one substance is dissolved in another * Solution (equation), in mathematics ** Numerical solution, in numerical analysis, approximate solutions within specified error bounds * Soluti ...
is enough to prove this existential quantification as being true. In contrast, "For some
even number In mathematics, parity is the property of an integer of whether it is even or odd. An integer is even if it is a multiple of two, and odd if it is not.. For example, −4, 0, 82 are even because \begin -2 \cdot 2 &= -4 \\ 0 \cdot 2 &= 0 \\ 41 ...
''n'', ''n''·''n'' = 25" is false, because there are no even solutions. The ''
domain of discourse In the formal sciences, the domain of discourse, also called the universe of discourse, universal set, or simply universe, is the set of entities over which certain variables of interest in some formal treatment may range. Overview The domain ...
'', which specifies the values the variable ''n'' is allowed to take, is therefore critical to a statement's trueness or falseness. Logical conjunctions are used to restrict the domain of discourse to fulfill a given predicate. For example: :
For some positive odd number ''n'', ''n''·''n'' = 25
is logically equivalent to :
For some natural number ''n'', ''n'' is odd and ''n''·''n'' = 25.
Here, "and" is the logical conjunction. In
symbolic logic Mathematical logic is the study of formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory. Research in mathematical logic commonly addresses the mathematical properties of formal ...
, "∃" (a rotated letter " E", in a
sans-serif In typography and lettering, a sans-serif, sans serif, gothic, or simply sans letterform is one that does not have extending features called "serifs" at the end of strokes. Sans-serif typefaces tend to have less stroke width variation than seri ...
font) is used to indicate existential quantification. Thus, if ''P''(''a'', ''b'', ''c'') is the predicate "''a''·''b'' = c", and \mathbb is the
set Set, The Set, SET or SETS may refer to: Science, technology, and mathematics Mathematics *Set (mathematics), a collection of elements *Category of sets, the category whose objects and morphisms are sets and total functions, respectively Electro ...
of natural numbers, then : \exists\mathbb\, P(n,n,25) is the (true) statement :
For some natural number ''n'', ''n''·''n'' = 25.
Similarly, if ''Q''(''n'') is the predicate "''n'' is even", then : \exists\mathbb\, \big(Q(n)\;\!\;\! \;\!\;\! P(n,n,25)\big) is the (false) statement :
For some natural number ''n'', ''n'' is even and ''n''·''n'' = 25.
In
mathematics Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics ...
, the proof of a "some" statement may be achieved either by a constructive proof, which exhibits an object satisfying the "some" statement, or by a nonconstructive proof, which shows that there must be such an object but without exhibiting one.


Properties


Negation

A quantified propositional function is a statement; thus, like statements, quantified functions can be negated. The \lnot\ symbol is used to denote negation. For example, if ''P''(''x'') is the predicate "''x'' is greater than 0 and less than 1", then, for a domain of discourse ''X'' of all natural numbers, the existential quantification "There exists a natural number ''x'' which is greater than 0 and less than 1" can be symbolically stated as: :\exists\mathbf\, P(x) This can be demonstrated to be false. Truthfully, it must be said, "It is not the case that there is a natural number ''x'' that is greater than 0 and less than 1", or, symbolically: :\lnot\ \exists\mathbf\, P(x). If there is no element of the domain of discourse for which the statement is true, then it must be false for all of those elements. That is, the negation of :\exists\mathbf\, P(x) is logically equivalent to "For any natural number ''x'', ''x'' is not greater than 0 and less than 1", or: :\forall\mathbf\, \lnot P(x) Generally, then, the negation of a propositional function's existential quantification is a universal quantification of that propositional function's negation; symbolically, :\lnot\ \exists\mathbf\, P(x) \equiv\ \forall\mathbf\, \lnot P(x) (This is a generalization of De Morgan's laws to predicate logic.) A common error is stating "all persons are not married" (i.e., "there exists no person who is married"), when "not all persons are married" (i.e., "there exists a person who is not married") is intended: :\lnot\ \exists\mathbf\, P(x) \equiv\ \forall\mathbf\, \lnot P(x) \not\equiv\ \lnot\ \forall\mathbf\, P(x) \equiv\ \exists\mathbf\, \lnot P(x) Negation is also expressible through a statement of "for no", as opposed to "for some": :\nexists\mathbf\, P(x) \equiv \lnot\ \exists\mathbf\, P(x) Unlike the universal quantifier, the existential quantifier distributes over logical disjunctions: \exists\mathbf\, P(x) \lor Q(x) \to\ (\exists\mathbf\, P(x) \lor \exists\mathbf\, Q(x))


Rules of Inference

A
rule of inference In the philosophy of logic, a rule of inference, inference rule or transformation rule is a logical form consisting of a function which takes premises, analyzes their syntax, and returns a conclusion (or conclusions). For example, the rule of in ...
is a rule justifying a logical step from hypothesis to conclusion. There are several rules of inference which utilize the existential quantifier. '' Existential introduction'' (∃I) concludes that, if the propositional function is known to be true for a particular element of the domain of discourse, then it must be true that there exists an element for which the proposition function is true. Symbolically, : P(a) \to\ \exists\mathbf\, P(x)
Existential instantiation In predicate logic, existential instantiation (also called existential elimination)Moore and Parker is a rule of inference which says that, given a formula of the form (\exists x) \phi(x), one may infer \phi(c) for a new constant symbol ''c''. Th ...
, when conducted in a Fitch style deduction, proceeds by entering a new sub-derivation while substituting an existentially quantified variable for a subject—which does not appear within any active sub-derivation. If a conclusion can be reached within this sub-derivation in which the substituted subject does not appear, then one can exit that sub-derivation with that conclusion. The reasoning behind existential elimination (∃E) is as follows: If it is given that there exists an element for which the proposition function is true, and if a conclusion can be reached by giving that element an arbitrary name, that conclusion is
necessarily true Logical truth is one of the most fundamental concepts in logic. Broadly speaking, a logical truth is a statement which is true regardless of the truth or falsity of its constituent propositions. In other words, a logical truth is a statement whic ...
, as long as it does not contain the name. Symbolically, for an arbitrary ''c'' and for a proposition ''Q'' in which ''c'' does not appear: : \exists\mathbf\, P(x) \to\ ((P(c) \to\ Q) \to\ Q) P(c) \to\ Q must be true for all values of ''c'' over the same domain ''X''; else, the logic does not follow: If ''c'' is not arbitrary, and is instead a specific element of the domain of discourse, then stating ''P''(''c'') might unjustifiably give more information about that object.


The empty set

The formula \exists \varnothing \, P(x) is always false, regardless of ''P''(''x''). This is because \varnothing denotes the
empty set In mathematics, the empty set is the unique set having no elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exists by including an axiom of empty set, while in other ...
, and no ''x'' of any description – let alone an ''x'' fulfilling a given predicate ''P''(''x'') – exist in the empty set. See also Vacuous truth for more information.


As adjoint

In
category theory Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations that was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Nowadays, cate ...
and the theory of elementary topoi, the existential quantifier can be understood as the left adjoint of a functor between power sets, the inverse image functor of a function between sets; likewise, the
universal quantifier In mathematical logic, a universal quantification is a type of quantifier, a logical constant which is interpreted as "given any" or "for all". It expresses that a predicate can be satisfied by every member of a domain of discourse. In other w ...
is the right adjoint. Saunders Mac Lane, Ieke Moerdijk, (1992): ''Sheaves in Geometry and Logic'' Springer-Verlag . ''See p. 58''.


Encoding

In Unicode and HTML, symbols are encoded and . In TeX, the symbol is produced with "\exists".


See also

* Existential clause *
Existence theorem In mathematics, an existence theorem is a theorem which asserts the existence of a certain object. It might be a statement which begins with the phrase " there exist(s)", or it might be a universal statement whose last quantifier is existential ...
* First-order logic *
Lindström quantifier In mathematical logic, a Lindström quantifier is a generalized polyadic quantifier. Lindström quantifiers generalize first-order quantifiers, such as the existential quantifier, the universal quantifier, and the counting quantifiers. They were ...
* List of logic symbols – for the unicode symbol ∃ * Quantifier variance * Uniqueness quantification


Notes


References

* {{Mathematical logic Logic symbols Quantifier (logic)