ω-consistent Theory
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematical logic Mathematical logic is the study of logic, formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory. Research in mathematical logic commonly addresses the mathematical properties of for ...
, an ω-consistent (or omega-consistent, also called numerically segregative)
W. V. O. Quine W. may refer to: * SoHo (Australian TV channel) (previously W.), an Australian pay television channel * ''W.'' (film), a 2008 American biographical drama film based on the life of George W. Bush * "W.", the fifth track from Codeine's 1992 EP ''Bar ...
(1971), ''Set Theory and Its Logic''.
theory is a
theory A theory is a rational type of abstract thinking about a phenomenon, or the results of such thinking. The process of contemplative and rational thinking is often associated with such processes as observational study or research. Theories may be s ...
(collection of
sentences ''The Four Books of Sentences'' (''Libri Quattuor Sententiarum'') is a book of theology written by Peter Lombard in the 12th century. It is a systematic compilation of theology, written around 1150; it derives its name from the ''sententiae'' o ...
) that is not only (syntactically)
consistent In classical deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. The lack of contradiction can be defined in either semantic or syntactic terms. The semantic definition states that a theory is consistent i ...
(that is, does not prove a
contradiction In traditional logic, a contradiction occurs when a proposition conflicts either with itself or established fact. It is often used as a tool to detect disingenuous beliefs and bias. Illustrating a general tendency in applied logic, Aristotle's ...
), but also avoids proving certain infinite combinations of sentences that are intuitively contradictory. The name is due to
Kurt Gödel Kurt Friedrich Gödel ( , ; April 28, 1906 â€“ January 14, 1978) was a logician, mathematician, and philosopher. Considered along with Aristotle and Gottlob Frege to be one of the most significant logicians in history, Gödel had an imme ...
, who introduced the concept in the course of proving the
incompleteness theorem Complete may refer to: Logic * Completeness (logic) * Completeness of a theory, the property of a theory that every formula in the theory's language or its negation is provable Mathematics * The completeness of the real numbers, which implies t ...
.


Definition

A theory ''T'' is said to
interpret Interpreting is a translational activity in which one produces a first and final target-language output on the basis of a one-time exposure to an expression in a source language. The most common two modes of interpreting are simultaneous interp ...
the
language Language is a structured system of communication. The structure of a language is its grammar and the free components are its vocabulary. Languages are the primary means by which humans communicate, and may be conveyed through a variety of met ...
of arithmetic if there is a translation of formulas of arithmetic into the language of ''T'' so that ''T'' is able to prove the basic axioms of the
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are those numbers used for counting (as in "there are ''six'' coins on the table") and ordering (as in "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country"). Numbers used for counting are called ''Cardinal n ...
s under this translation. A ''T'' that interprets arithmetic is ω-inconsistent if, for some property ''P'' of natural numbers (defined by a formula in the language of ''T''), ''T'' proves ''P''(0), ''P''(1), ''P''(2), and so on (that is, for every standard natural number ''n'', ''T'' proves that ''P''(''n'') holds), but ''T'' also proves that there is some natural number ''n'' (necessarily nonstandard in any
model A model is an informative representation of an object, person or system. The term originally denoted the Plan_(drawing), plans of a building in late 16th-century English, and derived via French and Italian ultimately from Latin ''modulus'', a mea ...
for ''T'') such that ''P''(''n'') ''fails''. This may not generate a contradiction within ''T'' because ''T'' may not be able to prove for any ''specific'' value of ''n'' that ''P''(''n'') fails, only that there ''is'' such an ''n''. ''T'' is ω-consistent if it is ''not'' ω-inconsistent. There is a weaker but closely related property of Σ1-soundness. A theory ''T'' is Σ1-sound (or 1-consistent, in another terminology) if every Σ01-sentence provable in ''T'' is true in the standard model of arithmetic N (i.e., the structure of the usual natural numbers with addition and multiplication). If ''T'' is strong enough to formalize a reasonable model of
computation Computation is any type of arithmetic or non-arithmetic calculation that follows a well-defined model (e.g., an algorithm). Mechanical or electronic devices (or, historically, people) that perform computations are known as ''computers''. An es ...
, Σ1-soundness is equivalent to demanding that whenever ''T'' proves that a
Turing machine A Turing machine is a mathematical model of computation describing an abstract machine that manipulates symbols on a strip of tape according to a table of rules. Despite the model's simplicity, it is capable of implementing any computer algori ...
''C'' halts, then ''C'' actually halts. Every ω-consistent theory is Σ1-sound, but not vice versa. More generally, we can define an analogous concept for higher levels of the
arithmetical hierarchy In mathematical logic, the arithmetical hierarchy, arithmetic hierarchy or Kleene–Mostowski hierarchy (after mathematicians Stephen Cole Kleene and Andrzej Mostowski) classifies certain sets based on the complexity of formulas that define th ...
. If Γ is a set of arithmetical sentences (typically Σ0''n'' for some ''n''), a theory ''T'' is Γ-sound if every Γ-sentence provable in ''T'' is true in the standard model. When Γ is the set of all arithmetical formulas, Γ-soundness is called just (arithmetical)
soundness In logic or, more precisely, deductive reasoning, an argument is sound if it is both valid in form and its premises are true. Soundness also has a related meaning in mathematical logic, wherein logical systems are sound if and only if every formul ...
. If the language of ''T'' consists ''only'' of the language of arithmetic (as opposed to, for example,
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly conce ...
), then a sound system is one whose model can be thought of as the set ω, the usual set of mathematical natural numbers. The case of general ''T'' is different, see
ω-logic In set theory, Ω-logic is an infinitary logic and deductive system proposed by as part of an attempt to generalize the theory of determinacy of pointclasses to cover the structure H_. Just as the axiom of projective determinacy yields a canoni ...
below. Σ''n''-soundness has the following computational interpretation: if the theory proves that a program ''C'' using a Σ''n''−1-
oracle An oracle is a person or agency considered to provide wise and insightful counsel or prophetic predictions, most notably including precognition of the future, inspired by deities. As such, it is a form of divination. Description The word '' ...
halts, then ''C'' actually halts.


Examples


Consistent, ω-inconsistent theories

Write PA for the theory
Peano arithmetic In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly u ...
, and Con(PA) for the statement of arithmetic that formalizes the claim "PA is consistent". Con(PA) could be of the form "For every natural number ''n'', ''n'' is not the Gödel number of a proof from PA that 0=1". (This formulation uses 0=1 instead of a direct contradiction; that gives the same result, because PA certainly proves ¬0=1, so if it proved 0=1 as well we would have a contradiction, and on the other hand, if PA proves a contradiction, then it proves anything, including 0=1.) Now, assuming PA is really consistent, it follows that PA + Â¬Con(PA) is also consistent, for if it were not, then PA would prove Con(PA) (''reductio''), contradicting Gödel's second incompleteness theorem. However, PA + Â¬Con(PA) is ''not'' ω-consistent. This is because, for any particular natural number ''n'', PA + Â¬Con(PA) proves that ''n'' is not the Gödel number of a proof that 0=1 (PA itself proves that fact; the extra assumption ¬Con(PA) is not needed). However, PA + Â¬Con(PA) proves that, for ''some'' natural number ''n'', ''n'' ''is'' the Gödel number of such a proof (this is just a direct restatement of the claim ¬Con(PA)). In this example, the axiom ¬Con(PA) is Σ1, hence the system PA + Â¬Con(PA) is in fact Σ1-unsound, not just ω-inconsistent.


Arithmetically sound, ω-inconsistent theories

Let ''T'' be PA together with the axioms ''c'' â‰  ''n'' for each natural number ''n'', where ''c'' is a new constant added to the language. Then ''T'' is arithmetically sound (as any nonstandard model of PA can be expanded to a model of ''T''), but ω-inconsistent (as it proves \exists x\,c=x, and ''c'' â‰  ''n'' for every number ''n''). Σ1-sound ω-inconsistent theories using only the language of arithmetic can be constructed as follows. Let ''I''Σ''n'' be the subtheory of PA with the induction schema restricted to Σ''n''-formulas, for any ''n'' > 0. The theory ''I''Σ''n'' + 1 is finitely axiomatizable, let thus ''A'' be its single axiom, and consider the theory ''T'' = ''I''Σ''n'' + Â¬''A''. We can assume that ''A'' is an instance of the induction schema, which has the form ::\forall w\, (0,w)\land\forall x\,(B(x,w)\to B(x+1,w))\to\forall x\,B(x,w) If we denote the formula ::\forall w\, (0,w)\land\forall x\,(B(x,w)\to B(x+1,w))\to B(n,w)/math> by ''P''(''n''), then for every natural number ''n'', the theory ''T'' (actually, even the pure predicate calculus) proves ''P''(''n''). On the other hand, ''T'' proves the formula \exists x\,\neg P(x), because it is
logically equivalent Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the science of deductively valid inferences or of logical truths. It is a formal science investigating how conclusions follow from premises ...
to the axiom ¬''A''. Therefore, ''T'' is ω-inconsistent. It is possible to show that ''T'' is Π''n'' + 3-sound. In fact, it is Π''n'' + 3-
conservative Conservatism is a cultural, social, and political philosophy that seeks to promote and to preserve traditional institutions, practices, and values. The central tenets of conservatism may vary in relation to the culture and civilization i ...
over the (obviously sound) theory ''I''Σ''n''. The argument is more complicated (it relies on the provability of the Σ''n'' + 2-
reflection principle In set theory, a branch of mathematics, a reflection principle says that it is possible to find sets that resemble the class of all sets. There are several different forms of the reflection principle depending on exactly what is meant by "resemble ...
for ''I''Σ''n'' in ''I''Σ''n'' + 1).


Arithmetically unsound, ω-consistent theories

Let ω-Con(PA) be the arithmetical sentence formalizing the statement "PA is ω-consistent". Then the theory PA + Â¬Ï‰-Con(PA) is unsound (Σ3-unsound, to be precise), but ω-consistent. The argument is similar to the first example: a suitable version of the
Hilbert David Hilbert (; ; 23 January 1862 – 14 February 1943) was a German mathematician, one of the most influential mathematicians of the 19th and early 20th centuries. Hilbert discovered and developed a broad range of fundamental ideas in many ...
– Bernays– Löb derivability conditions holds for the "provability predicate" ω-Prov(''A'') = Â¬Ï‰-Con(PA + Â¬''A''), hence it satisfies an analogue of Gödel's second incompleteness theorem.


ω-logic

The concept of theories of arithmetic whose integers are the true mathematical integers is captured by ω-logic. Let ''T'' be a theory in a
countable In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbers; ...
language that includes a unary predicate symbol ''N'' intended to hold just of the natural numbers, as well as specified names 0, 1, 2, ..., one for each (standard) natural number (which may be separate constants, or constant terms such as 0, 1, 1+1, 1+1+1, ..., etc.). Note that ''T'' itself could be referring to more general objects, such as
real number In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a ''continuous'' one-dimensional quantity such as a distance, duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that values can have arbitrarily small variations. Every real ...
s or sets; thus in a model of ''T'' the objects satisfying ''N''(''x'') are those that ''T'' interprets as natural numbers, not all of which need be named by one of the specified names. The system of ω-logic includes all axioms and rules of the usual first-order predicate logic, together with, for each ''T''-formula ''P''(''x'') with a specified free variable ''x'', an
infinitary In mathematics and logic, an operation is finitary if it has finite arity, i.e. if it has a finite number of input values. Similarly, an infinitary operation is one with an infinite number of input values. In standard mathematics, an operation ...
ω-rule of the form: :From P(0),P(1),P(2),\ldots infer \forall x\,(N(x)\to P(x)). That is, if the theory asserts (i.e. proves) ''P''(''n'') separately for each natural number ''n'' given by its specified name, then it also asserts ''P'' collectively for all natural numbers at once via the evident finite universally quantified counterpart of the infinitely many antecedents of the rule. For a theory of arithmetic, meaning one with intended domain the natural numbers such as
Peano arithmetic In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly u ...
, the predicate ''N'' is redundant and may be omitted from the language, with the consequent of the rule for each ''P'' simplifying to \forall x\,P(x). An ω-model of ''T'' is a model of ''T'' whose domain includes the natural numbers and whose specified names and symbol ''N'' are standardly interpreted, respectively as those numbers and the predicate having just those numbers as its domain (whence there are no nonstandard numbers). If ''N'' is absent from the language then what would have been the domain of ''N'' is required to be that of the model, i.e. the model contains only the natural numbers. (Other models of ''T'' may interpret these symbols nonstandardly; the domain of ''N'' need not even be countable, for example.) These requirements make the ω-rule sound in every ω-model. As a corollary to the
omitting types theorem In model theory and related areas of mathematics, a type is an object that describes how a (real or possible) element or finite collection of elements in a structure (mathematical logic), mathematical structure might behave. More precisely, it is ...
, the converse also holds: the theory ''T'' has an ω-model if and only if it is consistent in ω-logic. There is a close connection of ω-logic to ω-consistency. A theory consistent in ω-logic is also ω-consistent (and arithmetically sound). The converse is false, as consistency in ω-logic is a much stronger notion than ω-consistency. However, the following characterization holds: a theory is ω-consistent if and only if its closure under ''unnested'' applications of the ω-rule is consistent.


Relation to other consistency principles

If the theory ''T'' is recursively axiomatizable, ω-consistency has the following characterization, due to Craig SmoryÅ„ski: Reviewed in :''T'' is ω-consistent if and only if T+\mathrm_T+\mathrm_(\mathbb N) is consistent. Here, \mathrm_(\mathbb N) is the set of all Π02-sentences valid in the standard model of arithmetic, and \mathrm_T is the uniform reflection principle for ''T'', which consists of the axioms :\forall x\,(\mathrm_T(\ulcorner\varphi(\dot x)\urcorner)\to\varphi(x)) for every formula \varphi with one free variable. In particular, a finitely axiomatizable theory ''T'' in the language of arithmetic is ω-consistent if and only if ''T'' + PA is \Sigma^0_2-sound.


Notes


Bibliography

* Kurt Gödel (1931). 'Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I'. In ''Monatshefte für Mathematik''. Translated into English as
On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems "Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I" ("On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems I") is a paper in mathematical logic by Kurt Gödel. Submitted November ...
. {{DEFAULTSORT:Omega consistent theory Proof theory