Ogden's Lemma
In the theory of formal languages, Ogden's lemma (named after William F. Ogden) is a generalization of the pumping lemma for context-free languages. Despite Ogden's lemma being a strengthening of the pumping lemma, it is insufficient to fully characterize the class of context-free languages. This is in contrast to the Myhill–Nerode theorem, which unlike the pumping lemma for regular languages is a necessary and sufficient condition for regularity. Statement We will use underlines to indicate "marked" positions. Special cases Ogden's lemma is often stated in the following form, which can be obtained by "forgetting about" the grammar, and concentrating on the language itself: If a language is context-free, then there exists some number p\geq 1 (where may or may not be a pumping length) such that for any string of length at least in and every way of "marking" or more of the positions in , can be written as :s = uvwxy with strings and , such that # has at least one mar ... [...More Info...]       [...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]   |
|
Formal Language
In logic, mathematics, computer science, and linguistics, a formal language is a set of strings whose symbols are taken from a set called "alphabet". The alphabet of a formal language consists of symbols that concatenate into strings (also called "words"). Words that belong to a particular formal language are sometimes called ''well-formed words''. A formal language is often defined by means of a formal grammar such as a regular grammar or context-free grammar. In computer science, formal languages are used, among others, as the basis for defining the grammar of programming languages and formalized versions of subsets of natural languages, in which the words of the language represent concepts that are associated with meanings or semantics. In computational complexity theory, decision problems are typically defined as formal languages, and complexity classes are defined as the sets of the formal languages that can be parsed by machines with limited computational power. In ... [...More Info...]       [...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]   |
|
Pumping Lemma For Context-free Languages
In computer science, in particular in formal language theory, the pumping lemma for context-free languages, also known as the Bar-Hillel lemma, is a lemma that gives a property shared by all context-free languages and generalizes the pumping lemma for regular languages. The pumping lemma can be used to construct a refutation by contradiction that a specific language is ''not'' context-free. Conversely, the pumping lemma does not suffice to guarantee that a language ''is'' context-free; there are other necessary conditions, such as Ogden's lemma, or the Interchange lemma. Formal statement If a language L is context-free, then there exists some integer p \geq 1 (called a "pumping length") (Also see s, \geq p) can be written as : s = uvwxy with substrings u, v, w, x and y, such that : 1. , vx, \geq 1, : 2. , vwx, \leq p, and : 3. uv^n wx^n y \in L for all n \geq 0. Below is a formal expression of the Pumping Lemma. \begin ... [...More Info...]       [...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]   |
|
Myhill–Nerode Theorem
In the theory of formal languages, the Myhill–Nerode theorem provides a necessary and sufficient condition for a language to be regular. The theorem is named for John Myhill and Anil Nerode, who proved it at the University of Chicago in 1957 . Statement Given a language L, and a pair of strings x and y, define a distinguishing extension to be a string z such that exactly one of the two strings xz and yz belongs to L. Define a relation \sim_L on strings as x\; \sim_L\ y if there is no distinguishing extension for x and y. It is easy to show that \sim_L is an equivalence relation on strings, and thus it divides the set of all strings into equivalence classes. The Myhill–Nerode theorem states that a language L is regular if and only if \sim_L has a finite number of equivalence classes, and moreover, that this number is equal to the number of states in the minimal deterministic finite automaton (DFA) accepting L. Furthermore, every minimal DFA for the language is isomorphic t ... [...More Info...]       [...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]   |
|
Pumping Lemma For Regular Languages
In the theory of formal languages, the pumping lemma for regular languages is a Lemma (mathematics), lemma that describes an essential property of all regular languages. Informally, it says that all sufficiently long string (computer science), strings in a regular language may be ''pumped''—that is, have a middle section of the string repeated an arbitrary number of times—to produce a new string that is also part of the language. The pumping lemma is useful for proving that a specific language is not a regular language, by showing that the language does not have the property. Specifically, the pumping lemma says that for any regular language L, there exists a constant p such that any string w in L with length at least p can be split into three substrings x, y and z (w = xyz, with y being non-empty), such that the strings xz, xyz, xyyz, xyyyz, ... are also in L. The process of repeating y zero or more times is known as "pumping". Moreover, the pumping lemma guarantees that the ... [...More Info...]       [...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]   |
|
Context-free Grammar
In formal language theory, a context-free grammar (CFG) is a formal grammar whose production rules can be applied to a nonterminal symbol regardless of its context. In particular, in a context-free grammar, each production rule is of the form : A\ \to\ \alpha with A a ''single'' nonterminal symbol, and \alpha a string of terminals and/or nonterminals (\alpha can be empty). Regardless of which symbols surround it, the single nonterminal A on the left hand side can always be replaced by \alpha on the right hand side. This distinguishes it from a context-sensitive grammar, which can have production rules in the form \alpha A \beta \rightarrow \alpha \gamma \beta with A a nonterminal symbol and \alpha, \beta, and \gamma strings of terminal and/or nonterminal symbols. A formal grammar is essentially a set of production rules that describe all possible strings in a given formal language. Production rules are simple replacements. For example, the first rule in the picture, : \lan ... [...More Info...]       [...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]   |
|
Ambiguous Grammar
In computer science, an ambiguous grammar is a context-free grammar for which there exists a string (computer science), string that can have more than one leftmost derivation or parse tree. Every non-empty context-free language admits an ambiguous grammar by introducing e.g. a duplicate rule. A language that only admits ambiguous grammars is called an #Inherently ambiguous languages, inherently ambiguous language. Deterministic context-free grammars are always unambiguous, and are an important subclass of unambiguous grammars; there are non-deterministic unambiguous grammars, however. For computer programming languages, the reference grammar is often ambiguous, due to issues such as the dangling else problem. If present, these ambiguities are generally resolved by adding precedence rules or other context-sensitive grammar, context-sensitive parsing rules, so the overall phrase grammar is unambiguous. Some parsing algorithms (such as Earley parser, Earley or Generalized LR parser, GL ... [...More Info...]       [...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]   |
|
Post's Correspondence Problem
The Post correspondence problem is an undecidable decision problem that was introduced by Emil Post in 1946. Because it is simpler than the halting problem and the ''Entscheidungsproblem'' it is often used in proofs of undecidability. Definition of the problem Let A be an alphabet with at least two symbols. The input of the problem consists of two finite lists \alpha_, \ldots, \alpha_ and \beta_, \ldots, \beta_ of words over A. A solution to this problem is a sequence of indices (i_k)_ with K \ge 1 and 1 \le i_k \le N for all k, such that : \alpha_ \ldots \alpha_ = \beta_ \ldots \beta_. The decision problem then is to decide whether such a solution exists or not. Alternative definition :g: (i_1,\ldots,i_K) \mapsto \alpha_ \ldots \alpha_ :h: (i_1,\ldots,i_K) \mapsto \beta_ \ldots \beta_. This gives rise to an equivalent alternative definition often found in the literature, according to which any two homomorphisms g,h with a common domain and a common codomain form an i ... [...More Info...]       [...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]   |
|
Formal Languages
In logic, mathematics, computer science, and linguistics, a formal language is a set of string (computer science), strings whose symbols are taken from a set called "#Definition, alphabet". The alphabet of a formal language consists of symbols that concatenate into strings (also called "words"). Words that belong to a particular formal language are sometimes called Formal language#Definition, ''well-formed words''. A formal language is often defined by means of a formal grammar such as a regular grammar or context-free grammar. In computer science, formal languages are used, among others, as the basis for defining the grammar of programming languages and formalized versions of subsets of natural languages, in which the words of the language represent concepts that are associated with meanings or semantics. In computational complexity theory, decision problems are typically defined as formal languages, and complexity classes are defined as the sets of the formal languages that ... [...More Info...]       [...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]   |